Spencer Heath's
Series
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 2037
Transcription of a conversation between Heath and Alvin Lowi, Jr. at the latter’s home at 4018 Merrill Street, Torrance, California. Alvin’s wife, Guillermina, and Mrs. Frances Norton Manning, Heath’s hostess in Southern California who arranged and taped this meeting, were also present although mostly in another part of the house.
January 7, 1962
ALVIN LOWI, JR.: Now we were talking about . . .
SPENCER HEATH: Imagination. We were talking about absent-mindedness?
A: (Laughing)
S: I was about to say, that my mind travels in so many far places, that that’s the reason it’s absent so much of the time.
A: I have a few misgivings about going into business, because of my absent-mindedness .. I mean I’m aware of it because of my preference to think about abstractions, and about hypotheses and theories and .. well let’s say to attempt inductions, as apart from deduction about immediate effects of things.
S: Abstractions can crowd out your concretions, eh?
A: Yes sir.
S: Concrete things are the things most people pay attention to. The only interesting thing about things, in my view, is the ideas behind them. As I see it, all things represent ideas. And it’s the idea represented by the thing that is the great center of interest.
A: Well you don’t have things without ideas. At least without ideas the only things that you have are those things which were here before we got here — the
primordial material, you might say. Other than that there are no other things, as I see it, without ideas — without human ideas, to be specific.
S: I dare say the primordial material in us was here before we got here ourselves.
A: Oh, I’m sure that it was. That sticks too; as far as humans are concerned we can only hope to make the best use of what is here, and so far, we don’t have any prospects of running out of this material as I see it.
S: I think I have a very good prospect at my 86 years of age; I think I have a very good prospect of running out. /both laughing/
A: Well it seems impossible, but I know biologically that it must be.
/Interruption to check tape recorder/
S: You were suggesting that the primordial thing didn’t have any ideas.
A: But before that I would like to say for posterity that I hope you have many many happy returns of the day, of last Wednesday. Your 86th, I believe it was.
S: As Clarence Darrow told the judge when he said, “I hope you’re not going
to be in contempt,” Darrow said, “Well Your Honor can always hope.” (both
laughing) So if you’re hoping I’m going to have many happy returns, you
can always hope. You can have some of that hope when you haven’t got
anything else.
A: That’s right. There’s always got to be. I expect even the most miserable specimen has hope. If he doesn’t, he’s only living biologically ..
S: And when he gives up hope, he gives up life.
A: Yes ..
S: He has no hold on life without it.
A: He’s just vegetative, I would say.
S: Yes. If he gives up in any life of his mind, or life of imagination . . Of course some of his vital functions might go on — vegetatively as you say — but human beings, we live by our imagination. And when imagination goes broke, why then we lapse back to the animal level.
A: That goes for a society as well as an individual, I think. As soon as the prevailing trend in society is a departure from imaginative, or at least a toleration of imaginative ideas, I think you may say that society is in a full-fledged regression .. as soon as this becomes noticeable. Which it is to us now. I have not always been quite so aware of it as I am now but I’m still, I would say, in the very, very small minority of people who can see that what people are calling ideas these days are not really; it’s just talk. It’s just noise.
S: For my part, I don’t see that civilization is in any decline. There may be periods, little lumps in the curve, little humped sticks in the curve ________, but this is an expanding universe, expanding both quantitatively and qualitatively.
A: Well technologically speaking, I would say it’s progressive. But socially speaking, I can’t say that we’re having any progress that’s measurable. Locally in spots, maybe, but in any larger amount I wouldn’t say that I could see any social progress.
S: Walk into a tropical rain forest, and you’ll find a great many trees lying flat on the ground in various stages of decay, and dissolution, with many parasites living on them perhaps. And parasites living on the living trees, and so on. And pulling trees down. Of course when the tree’s down then the parasite has to die, as all parasites have to expire with the host, apparently. So if we walk through a forest like that, no matter how far, and confine our attention to the trees that are lying down and don’t notice the ones that are standing up, except to notice that they are being pulled down, and on their way down, you will never see anything but dissolution and decay. We’d have to be pretty blind in one eye not to notice that trees were growing, wouldn’t we?
A: Yes, we would.
S: And that every time a tree came down there were young ones taking their place and so on. And so in our civilization, today. If we only look at the things that are falling down, we won’t think anything is going up.
A: So you look at this as something that is characteristic of the type of equilibrium that we have on this planet; that the type of equilibrium that exists is one which is on the average advancing towards a better stage. And I’m not defining better now. But it’s on the average going that way, that’s the prevailing trend. But there are oscillations in this equilibrium which, if you’re on the regressive side of this oscillation, why it looks pretty bleak, and if you’re on the advancing side of it, it looks pretty good.
S: Equilibrium is a thing I’m not very fond of myself, because equilibrium it seems to me — unless you mean a dynamic equilibrium — equilibrium is a static condition.
A: Well I mean dynamic equilibrium. To me equilibrium is not a static concept.
S: As long as you mean a dynamic equilibrium, then whatever forces are involved are going somewhere. And that we call progress. Let me give you an illustration of that: you and I are confronted by a stone wall. We want to get over it. And so I try jumping. And jumping doesn’t do much good; I can’t get my feet very far off the ground. So I reach down and pull on my bootstraps, and that doesn’t seem to help very much, and after a good many fumblings around and trying empirically you know, cutting and trying, fumbling and success, finally one of us has a happy idea. Let’s pull on each other’s boot straps. Now, we’re still in equilibrium; it’s just that we’re going somewhere now. Whereas before when we pulled on our own bootstraps we were in static equilibrium Now, as we pull on each other’s bootstraps, we’re still in equilibrium, but it’s a dynamic equilibrium; we’re going somewhere and so may get over the wall. And I think that the cosmos itself is in a dynamic equilibrium, and it can go in any direction, indefinitely, without ever coming to any___________. There’s no reason why it couldn’t keep on going, in respect to any matter.
A: Well I was careless. I should have said dynamic equilibrium, because what I have in mind is something analogous to a spring mass, a mass hanging on a spring.
/Interruption, Mina suggesting they move to another room where it will be less noisy/
A: These couches [couches that Alvin had made] which fold into … You’re interested in mechanisms, but they work very well. I’m rather proud of these. They have a four-bar link. /Sound of moving furniture about/
S: That’s a very neat kind of a toggle. That kind of a toggle might have utility elsewhere than in furniture.
. . . . . . . . .
A: Well I find the term, “Burke’s Principle” . . it belongs to Joseph Galambos, but I find it very useful myself to use, because it . .
S: A quotation we’ve heard often. Is it thought to have originated with Burke?
A: The quotation? Well it’s described of Burke.
S: Is it. I didn’t remember about that. I’d heard it often.
A: So I keep saying that it belongs to Burke.
S: It might as well.
A: As far as I know .. I’m not well read on Burke .. he deserves it. I see no reason why he shouldn’t get the credit for it. I tend not to question historians too much until I’ve personally researched the matter a little bit more myself. I’m not taking everything they say on faith, it’s just a matter of deference, you might say.
S: I think a few samples in a person’s writing, representative of different times of his life, are perfectly useful for most purposes. Just the same as if you take a few sample borings from a geological area, you don’t have to turn over all the strata to see what’s there; you can take samples here and there. Like a book; if you take samples from different parts of a book, you get the general tone of the book. Of course if it has a lot of detail that you want to follow up, then you want to read it in detail. But so it is with a man’s writings. Take some generous samples here and there at different times, and you’ve got his number. And that’s all you need for most purposes . . because people are, without knowing it themselves, are consistent.
A: I guess over a long period of time, if they are productive for a long period of time, you may notice some development in their…
S: Emerson says, let consistency be a hobgoblin of little minds. Let it be
gazetted henceforth forever — or something like that. Then he goes on to say, “Do thou so think and act as each moment goes by with complete sincerity, and never fear but what the pattern will be fair.” (laughing) It will make sense of itself. Whether you try to make it consistent or not. Of course some people are consistently bad. Some of the bad men of history have been consistently so. we find it very seldom that a man will spring all the way from the seraphic to the diabolic. He can’t take that much variation. But he’ll take his position somewhere near the angels or somewhere near the devils, and be pretty consistently at that level. (laughing) So happily, just as geologists don’t have to turn over all the layers — turn the thing all over upside down to see what’s there — because they can take samples at frequent intervals, so we can take samples of anybody’s writings, or anybody’s thought, or anybody’s conversation, and you get to know a person by more or less unconsciously synthesizing what he says, and he makes up a personality for you. You know him pretty well by a good deal of contact with him. Of course you can’t take a potshot here and there and generalize on small data.
A: People have thoughts, certainly.
S: Yes.
A: Well I suppose you could also say that you may find some several individuals who think a great deal alike, and in the perspective of the past, that is looking back many generations, it may be difficult, unless a man has a signed letter or some published work, it may be difficult to decide Just exactly who originated some saying or some document. For example the research that Joseph Lewis did on the Declaration of Independence, attempting to prove that Thomas Paine was the actual author instead of Jefferson, is a good example. Jefferson and Paine probably did think a great deal alike, and you would almost have to go into that kind of research on anything which was not precisely documented and published to be able to say with any certainty who it belonged to. Like, there’s this quotation, “Resistance to tyranny is obedience to God,” or “Resistance to tyrants is obedience to God,” has been ascribed variously to three or four, I think it’s three different individuals. I don’t recall now who they all were . . it’s been ascribed to Jefferson and Franklin maybe, and . . .
S: I’m not sure that’s very authentic though, because as I remember, God or one of His prime representatives said that we should resist not evil. If tyranny is evil, we should not resist it. But overcome evil with good. We have divine command not to resist it. So we can’t very well reconcile that with the idea that resistance to tyranny is obedience to God. (laughing)
A: Well, these people who have been attributed to having said this,
weren’t exactly Christians in the classical sense, so this is probably pretty good evidence to support the thesis that Jefferson was a Deist and not a Christian. Because that remark actually does, as you point out, contradict this basic Christian precept, it seems to me.
S: Yes. However I’m afraid it’s kind of a numbers game when we try to determine the exact authorship of things. Like the authorship of the New Testament. Like the authorship of Shakespeare. You know what the Irishman said about it?
A: No
S: “If it wasn’t Shakespeare wrote all those things it was another fellow
by the same name, and it’s just as good.”
A: (laughing)
S: So I don’t think it’s terribly important who said a thing or who said it first, or who said it last, or who ever said it at all.
A: When you get right down to it, this shouldn’t have anything to do with whether or not it’s a great piece of work, or whether it’s a miserable piece of work, or whether it’s worth remembering, or constructive, or creative . . .
S: I think during contemporary times, it could be fairly important, because we want to look to the same source for more. We want to encourage and inspire that person. We want to be inspired by him, we want to know who he is, and so on. You want to know your friends or any contemporary friends.
A: The devil of that is . . .
S: If you let a hundred years go by, what’s the difference with me whether David and Jonathan were good friends or David and somebody else. (laughing)
A: That’s a very keen observation, and I have another one I’d like to make. And that is, it’s very difficult to observe your contemporaries and be able to judge whether some of their ideas are really good or not, especially when it comes to the arts or to creative writing, and things like this. And you may never come in contact with them until after their death, and then through their writing, so that it’s usually in the perspective of history, you know as they say, you never know until a man’s dead whether his writings or anything that he created will live. And the people tend to take this for granted and make no attempt to determine in advance of their passing whether these things that they are doing are worthwhile or not. In fact they tend to poo poo everything that is done, just because they’ll wait: let posterity judge. And some, like the ones we were talking about a while ago, they’re not willing to let posterity judge — they condemn every innovator that comes along. I’m now referring to just those very few people who tolerate new ideas. They still tend to refuse to judge.
S: I suspect somewhat that people who accept new ideas are not always as judicious as they might be. They don’t always discriminate between whether . . perhaps they don’t always have the capacity to discriminate between good ideas and bad ideas. So that contemporary people are just as likely to preserve for posterity bad ideas, as good ideas. And moreover, I don’t think that just because ideas survive, that they’re necessarily good ones. Because I don’t know . . we have no means of knowing how many good ideas are dead and buried every day. We just don’t know about that. So we shouldn’t assume that the ones that live are good ones, and that all that didn’t live were bad . .
A: Yes, I guess you could worry yourself sick over how many really good ideas have been lost in history, just because . . Well, like I don’t know who originated the heliocentric theory of the solar system, but I know that it existed maybe two thousand years before Copernicus.
S: Well, we do know that Copernicus did figure out the mass, motion and time in it, put the arithmetic to it . . or discovered the arithmetic in it. And before that they had a whole lot of subjective nonsense and astrological notions full of animals and demons and dragons, and the twelve signs of the Zodiac and everything of that sort. But when . . .
A: Yes, but the concept of the sun being the center of the universe I guess, as they put it . . they didn’t know what these other bodies, these little particles out there were.
S: I imagine the sun worshippers were pretty favorable to that idea.
A: I expect so. But they were called heathens or something in those days. In the early . . .
S: Well, some people had to call them Heathen; they didn’t call themselves that probably, or anything opprobrious like that! (Chuckling)
A: But they weren’t looked on with a great deal of favor and respect.
S: In the eyes of the public the trouble with Copernicus was that he simplified things. Now the public don’t like things to be simplified; they want to be confused. Along came Galileo, and he made it simpler yet. He got down to the roots of the matter, the generalizations, the simple form of it that applied to the whole field of phenomena. Then along came Newton, and he found the whole thing ________in the whole solar system, the arithmetic was there just as plain as anything in the world. Anybody could understand it after that. Now I thought I was happier with the multiplication table, without knowing anything about it, as a kid. I didn’t think I ever could, anyway. It was too complicated. When I got into it, and got to about the second or third table, why it commenced to clear up to me. -—”Is that all there is to it!”
A: Did you build your own?
S: Yes certainly, and I was rather charmed at that. But people generally are not charmed at simplification. They say that’s oversimplifying. They’d rather have their false gods and their complicated ignorance. What they don’t understand, they rather cherish it. There’s a conservative tendency to cherish our ignorance, you know. Cherish our stupidity.
A: Yes, it’s a sacred cow of complexity.
S: Yes. It shouldn’t be looked into. Our physical science today suffers from that same thing.
A: Ever since Newton, they’ve been trying to complicate things again. Well, not across the board, but . . .
S: During this half century perhaps, during this twentieth century, they certainly have been complicating things. They’ve had some excuse for it . . .
A: Well there are of course a few individuals who didn’t, like Maxwell and _________.
S: I want to see our whole physical science recast on the basis of taking the least, the simplest a prioris it’s possible to take, and seeing what you can build with them. And then if you can’t build satisfactorily with the ones you start out with . . let’s say you take three, and you find you’ve come to the limit of explaining things in terms of those three, then give serious consideration to seeing if maybe you can find a fourth. Now all physical investigation depends upon discovering ratios — measurements in things. The minute you discover a ratio in any activity or any event, you call that a dimension, a ratio between a unit and the particular number that describes the thing. And so we go on examining dimensions of things. And if we examine a cube we find three different dimensions, but all of the same kind. If we examine an event we find three different dimensions, but of three different kinds. And when we can’t describe events adequately in the three known dimensions that are stated in our high school physics and so on as being the fundamental units of physical science, when we find those three units fail us, then it’s time to consider whether or not we can find another unit and get some kind of fourth dimension. And I think that until we have exhausted the resources of explaining things, understanding things, in terms of the three, we’ll be as badly off if we try to fool with a fourth as we would be trying to understand a cube by importing a fourth direction in the same dimensions.
A: Unless you’re deliberately experimenting with a fourth or a fifth or a sixth postulate.
S: Even so, you’d better begin with one . . .
A: You better be sure that you’ve exhausted yourself on the first three or however many you have . . .
S: Otherwise you’re violating the principle of simplicity — the simplest explanation. If you bring in four factors unnecessarily when three are sufficient, you’re violating the scientific rule of finding the simplest explanation of things.
A: Joseph Galambos calls this Occam’s razor. Have you ever heard of this expression?
S: Yes . . now wait a minute. Occam . . I can’t place it now though I remember I’ve heard the expression. Occam was one of those . . a William of Occam . . familiar names somewhere back in the Middle Ages; I can’t place him even in his time now. What does he say about him?
A: He calls this part of the scientific method — Occam’s Razor. And it’s stated like this . . I’m stating it in my own words: If you have two rival hypotheses that both explain a given domain of phenomena, choose the one which has the fewer postulates.
S: The least a priori’s.
A: Yes.
S: The simplest premises.
A: Yes. Choose the simpler.
S: And that’s called a razor?
A: That’s called Occam’s Razor.
S: Shave off the surplus! (laughing)
A: Shave off the fuzz.
S: That’s a very good one. I’ll have to try to remember that, because I’m very much committed to that point of view.
A: I know you are.
S: Exceedingly so. More so than anybody I know.
A: Well it’s a way of life. And to return to a point we were making earlier, it may be a fetish on my part — I don’t think so — but of all the things that bother me about the way things are, it’s this tendency to overcomplicate things, and to condemn those who would simplify, with the argument that, “Things are just not that simple, always.” This is one of the toughest things to bear for me that there is. And of course, it’s a natural phenomenon too; you might say it’s one of those basic social characteristics that might be called natural phenomena, I guess, that people always have tended to over-complicate things . . .
S: I think clear up to and through Newton, the tendency of understanding our environment was towards simpler conceptions — wider, broader generalizations and fewer elements or parts in them. But since Newton, we’ve been running to multifariousness in our premises. Well . . maybe we’re on the regressive swing of the dynamic stability we were talking about a little while ago since Newton. Insofar as intellectual things are concerned, perhaps not long after Newton the curve was swinging the other way, and maybe one of these days it will swing back the other way.
S: Of course our understanding of things, even our capacity to understand, can conceivably decline. But the rationale of the cosmos itself can’t be supposed to suffer from any such cause as that.
A: No. Of course not. It could care less.
S: (Laughing) It couldn’t care less! Yet we must not assume that we are not parts of the cosmos. We belong to the cosmos.
A: Oh, certainly.
S: We’re children of the cosmos. And what’s in the cosmos as a whole is in us, as the chip contains the elements of the block from which it is hewn. So that we’ll have to come back, in the long run . . the positive, the things that support life, will be more powerful than the things that destroy life. Light is more powerful than darkness — since darkness has no power at all. As you well know.
A: That’s right. But it’s a great source of agitation to people. I mean it becomes a way of life to some people just because it fills most of their psychological capacity with things like fear and hate. These can be all consuming, it seems to me. If a person wishes to live in the darkness, why he may fill up himself, he may fully occupy his capacities with such things, and live in the darkness.
S: He’s working with darkness? (Laughing)
A: But he’s still just subsisting.
S: I agree with you quite profoundly. Because I see that man is fundamentally, so far as physical man is concerned and his physical powers, including his power to reason . . are matters that had to grow. And that in the case of the man animal, the growth has far transcended that of the other animal forms. And that man is only man so far as he can be described in language that doesn’t apply to anything else — and when you can apply descriptive words to humans in common with other forms of life then you have not distinguished him; you have identified him with them. And so when we speak of man that all men are mortal, we are talking about animals. Because animals have to be mortal. They can have no dream, they don’t have the imaginative powers apparently, the picturing power, the imagination, to think of yesterday, nor tomorrow. They only live in today.
A: They can perceive, but they can’t conceive.
S: Exactly. Very well said. And so they are always headed for extinction, because they have no dream towards which to strive. And no powers wherewith to fulfill their dreams.
A: Either extinction or enslavement.
S: Yes. Precisely.
A: Which is to a human being the same thing, I would say.
S: Yes. Now a human being has powers far exceeding that; he’s liberated from that because he can travel into yesterday, and he can travel in tomorrow. He can hold in his mind things that exist nowhere else. That is, patterns of organization that exist nowhere else. And so having a dream, he can put forth effort towards the realization of that dream. So he’s distinguished from the animal. The only thing that can conceive immortality could ever practice it. And I’m convinced that human beings as a race cannot conceive of any dream, can’t aspire towards anything — over many generations — without it expressing what is native to their constitution. So they cannot dream anything that they cannot ultimately achieve.
A: Well this gets to a real basic point . . .
S: Because every achievement is an achievement of what is innate, what is potential in us. And we can only dream what is potential. I don’t mean a single individual, but I mean what is characteristic. Because nature is very variable . . . all living things are variable, you know. Variability and differentiation is a characteristic of life — no two leaves on the tree alike, and that sort of thing. So with individuals we can’t depend on similarities. But when you take statistically, take millions of people over thousands of years entertaining the same dream, why that’s the . . the dream itself is the first putting out of the energy towards its accomplishment.
A: If I may add a couple of points here that I think are relevant, I think that people can dream about things that are unattainable, that contradict the natural order, you might say. They can dream and shoot for these things. But if they do, over a few generations, they tend to produce regression. In other words, if they dream of Utopian things and try to put these into practice. If they aspire towards things which are not attainable from this point of view, then the mere pursuit of these goals will tend to reduce their own chances of survival. I think they can probably dream and aspire towards things which are not attainable for a few generations, but after a while certain effects start to set in which indicate that the ends that they are shooting for are not achievable or that they are not desirable when they start thinking of them in terms of the other effects that are taking place. The other point I was going to make is, that you were saying a while ago that man has to use a language or choose words which characterize his constitution. Suppose men deliberately. . .
S: I don’t remember saying it, but I’ll say it now.
A: Does that sound acceptable to you?
S: If I didn’t say it, I’ll say it now. (laughing)
A: All right, sir. Then suppose men deliberately choose to confuse their language, or to make their language less precise rather than more precise, they choose to confuse the meaning of words and prefer not to stick to a definition, they cultivate bringing in new shadings on the meanings of words and so forth. Then how does a man, under those conditions, characterize this constitution we’re talking about in such a way that he may define his goals?
S: We are all aware that there are those who seek darkness rather than light. There are those who seek death, rather than life. But they are too exceptional to characterize the whole.
A: Yes, they are.
S: There is no statistical validity in that. And since nature is discrete, and the units in any statistical complex are so small, then any judgment based upon the unit, the particular, is a generalization on insufficient data. We have to generalize on the whole.
A: Well I’m the product of a recent generation, and my observation is that, at least at the present time, there are a large number of people . . in fact I would say that I don’t think the people who promote the confusion of the language are in a majority. The majority goes along with them. Because it makes it possible for them to . . .
S: The blind leaders of the blind?
A: . . . explain away, or to apologize for their lack of articulateness, or ability to communicate. It gives them a ready excuse — “Words mean different things and so I don’t have to worry too much about it.”
S: And they can be j’iners and shine by some felt or reflected light. As they suppose.
A: There was a cartoon not too long ago, “The Portrait of a Bureaucrat,” by Virgil Parch. It was a picture of a bureau — like a chest of drawers, you know, with, a mirror on top? Here was a chest of drawers with legs and arms on it with a mirror, so this was supposed to be the portrait of a bureaucrat. You look into it and it reflects anything you wish to see.
S: (laughing) It reflects a whole lot of things I’d rather not see when I look at a bureaucrat. (both laughing) But your image makes me think of the frontispiece, I think it is, in one of Parkinson’s books about Parkinson’s Law, and all? The picture of a bureaucrat?
A: I don’t recall.
S: Well, it’s a very highly elaborated stuffed shirt — very obese and very blank, and very smug. (laughing)
A: Nobody has ever described bureaucrats in such detail as Parkinson, I don’t think.
S: No. (laughing) Probably so. Although we’ve had some pretty good jobs — Hawthorne described the bureaucrats in his Custom House tales, way back in his day. And it’s the same thing. When I was in England in the ‘thirties, I was taken into a big government office. You could almost see the cobwebs hanging on the wall, and you see the people all were past middle life. I asked my guide what kind of office this was, and he said, “This is the Office of Assessment.” I said, “Do they ever assess anything?” “No,” he said; “Back in Lloyd George’s day,” some twenty or thirty years before, “they were established in this office to assess land. The Parliament repealed the law assessing land, but they didn’t repeal the jobs. So they were still holding onto them. (laughter)
A: This is one of those perfect Parkinsonian organizations that receives an input but delivers no output.
S: Precisely.
A: Efficiency reaches absolute zero.
S: I’m not quite satisfied with your suggestion that Utopias are vain, because a Utopia always has to be the top dream of some form of life at some stage. And if we go back in our own ancestry we find that — and we don’t have to go back very far — that anybody who believed in such a thing as the room we’re sitting in now would be having a Utopian dream.
A: When I use the term “Utopia,” I mean something very specific. And so perhaps I’d better define it, right here. By “Utopia,” I mean that which is unattainable in this universe because it contradicts the structure of the universe. That’s what I mean by “Utopian.” A man may dream of something which is unattainable but he may not know it — maybe nobody knows it. Maybe it contradicts something natural which we have not yet defined sufficiently to be able to judge. But if it is ever known, that such an idea carries with it a contradiction of some natural principle, then it can be called Utopian. And the pursuit of it, the pursuit of this objective, would tend to reduce one’s chances of survival.
S: Yes, a self-contradictory statement, any statement that contains its own contradiction, has to be false. And this wouldn’t be a cosmos if there were events occurring that contradicted other events. A paradox just nullifies itself.
A: But in an idea, it may not be clear that a contradiction is implied in it. So people pursue a contradictory, or an unattainable, idea for a long time without noticing it.
S: Not everybody can see the contradiction in it. You know what the farm boy said when he told the Sunday School teacher he knew something God couldn’t do. He said, “What’s that, Johnny?” He said, “God can’t make a three-year-old cat in five minutes.” And not everybody would see the self-contradiction there, perhaps. You can see that?
A: Of course; it’s very basic.
S: It would be two different things, and He couldn’t make two different things at once. (Both laughing) And so, any statement that contains its own contradiction is patently false. And false by the way doesn’t mean contrary, it means reduced to zero. It doesn’t mean contrary in the sense of contrary, or oppositional, by going into a completely different direction. False means the self-destructive. And those things that we do in life that are self-destructive are the only false things.
A: This is almost precisely the definition of false which is being taught in this course.
S: Good.
A: The idea of truth and falsity is simply that which you can verify by
observation or you cannot. Of course observation is something which should be defined, but you can extend observation to include such things as deduction .. from physical observation.
S: Of course all experiment, even laboratory experiment, is only observation. You may prepare the circumstances, prepare the conditions, so a certain event happens, but the most you can do by way of understanding the event is to observe it. If it’s borne out by observation, why then you can verify it.
A: The verification involves some other powers of logic which are not contained in the experiment, though. The observer still has to use his mind, otherwise the verification can’t take place.
S: When you see something happening in nature, and you’re a careful observer and use the quantitative method, you put down numerical data, describing it. And then you take that numerical data into your own imagination, and you find it makes a whole lot of sense. You say, then, this is a natural law. The only reason you know it’s a natural law is because you have the same thing in your consciousness — you have the same arithmetic inside your head that you had in the train of gears, or in this lever out here. And then we come to understand our environment because we have the psyche carrying on the same kind of events intellectually, mentally, rationally, that are going on in the objective world. A one-to-one pattern, like the superposition of triangles, and so on. You have an identity there. And then moreover, our imagination is so various, so potential, that we can take those numerical data (and) by certain laws which we all agree upon, we can manipulate the data mathematically and discover that under some other circumstance, it would be thus and so. So by a process of deduction we can predict what’s going to happen in a situation that we’ve never experienced before.
A: And the deduction for you, and the deduction for me, to the extent we are successful at it, is the same. We don’t use it differently — or if we do, one of us is wrong.
S: And that one will admit it, too, because we can’t have two arithmetics.
A: If he’s honest.
S: Well, of course you have to assume that he’s trying to find out something. Not trying to cheat himself.
A: Yes.
S: So you can’t have a different arithmetic from mine, because it’s innate in us. The arithmetic is innate in a train of gears, isn’t it? Or in a lever, or a chemical reaction.
A: If it’s a train of gears.
S: — A thing which manifests itself to our sensory system as a train of gears, or a chemical reaction. We have the same arithmetic. And that shows that we have a solidarity with our cosmos. We are cosmic ourselves. We have the same characteristics as the whole cosmos, necessarily — and that doesn’t mean that we have them to the same extent, because the whole cosmos is infinite, and we know darn well we are not infinite. But so far as we go, we have the same rationality that’s in our environment. That’s what makes it possible for us to understand it.
A: It just exists in different human beings in different degrees.
S: And so I heard a man say one time — he shocked some of his associates — saying that everybody thinks exactly alike. They challenged him and he stood his ground on it and he finally said, “Well, thinking is a function of the brain. And digestion is a function of the stomach. Respiration is a function of the lungs,” and so on. He said, “I know some of us digest a whole lot more than others do; some of us breathe a whole lot more than others do. And I suspect that a lot of us think a lot more than than others do, but so far as they think, they’re all thinking the same way — the same as they digested the same way. (laughing)
A: That’s a very good way to put it, too. And you see, if you attempt to talk to a lot of people without in advance knowing that you have something in common with them, you run into this situation frequently, that people really believe that there are different kinds of logic. That this individual over here, his mind is constructed such that it works differently, and he may add up two and two and get four and that’s okay for him . . this is a trivial example.
S: It’s what you call relativity.
A: It’s like Marxian logic.
S: /One person sees a/ train at one velocity, for somebody else it’s another velocity.
A: But relativity doesn’t mean this! But, anyway, it’s said, and this is one of the idiotic things about Marxian theory, that any Marxian who can’t come to terms with his adversary, can always fall back on the argument that this other guy is using bourgeois logic. (both laughing) And that’s of course a different world. (both laughing) That’s a good excuse. That’s a very powerful excuse.
S: While our minds do run on the same rational principles, so long as we engage in that kind of activity at all, the rest of our psyche — at least 90 percent of it — doesn’t have any uniform behavior. Highly diverse. Our whole emotional make-up . . can run into all kinds of contradictions.
A: But this is not a function of the rational being.
S: No. It’s the functioning of the being that doesn’t have rational powers. The animal. It’s the functioning of the being that’s headed towards extinction.
A: I’ve never looked at it this way, but you’ve given me some powerful ideas. There is always the tendency to try to characterize social behavior — that is, macroscopic behavior of human beings — using psychology, which I consider is a microscopic thing. That is, psychology applies to individuals, to given human beings, whereas human action, or economics, applies to macroscopic samples of human beings. Large numbers of them.
S: Taken statistically.
A: Yes. And there’s always a tendency to describe the macroscopic behavior in terms of the microscopic quantities.
S: — to generalize on narrow premises.
A: We already know you get in trouble this way. There are some things you can do this way, like in thermodynamics. Not without statistics, though. You can take the microscopic models from kinetic theory of gases or of molecules, and by using statistics, you can describe macroscopic behavior. But not always; at least there is still a wide gap between this microscopic approach to describing processes in gases and in metals and liquids and things like this and in fluid dynamics, and the macroscopic approach.
S: Max Planck, for one, insists however that our inability to find the rationale in the very minute, is a characteristic of our powers of understanding, our perception, and not a characteristic of the minute event itself.
A: I would agree with that. Just because we can’t make the transformation between the microscopic to the macroscopic, doesn’t mean that this isn’t the way it happens. I agree with this.
S: It’s just they can’t reach that far down in the well; it doesn’t prove that there are no depths there — and no rationality.
A: Exactly. That there’s no bottom. (laughter) I don’t know who it was that related the remark of the fisherman who threw his net in the water — it was of a certain mesh, and he seined the ocean several times and came up with a fish that long, and he said, “There are no fish in the ocean smaller than this.” Well, to some extent the human being is limited by his senses to observations of certain classes. But with advances in those tools which extend the sensory capabilities, I wouldn’t place a limit on this. I would say this is likely to be ever expanding. We know of a large number of fundamental particles now — well at least mathematically, which have been verified by experiment — which are smaller than electrons, let’s say. You can’t hold them in your hand, of course; nobody’s ever seen an electron either. But we watch pictures created by theories which postulate a certain mathematical model for an electron, and they work. So, I see no reason to object to the idea of an electron — or even smaller particles, for the same reason.
S: We can deduce events from experienced events with a great deal of certainty — events which we cannot experience. The forming of a molecule by atoms, we can’t experience them.
A: But the induction of the idea that there are such things, and that they act this way, that comes about with much less frequency and much less reliability.
S: We have the same kind of certainty about scientific deductions that we have about geometrical deductions. Give us certain premises in a Euclid proposition, and by reasoning on those premises we deduce things with a great deal of certainty. Since that’s only in the realm of the imagination anyway, we can’t verify it in physical experience. But physicists have a weakness — a very strong weakness too, I think — to ascribe to the infinite environment limitations which exist only in us. We know that in all respects we are limited — in every possible respect we are limited — so far as our structure is concerned; so far as our sensory system is concerned. We also know that the imagination knows no bounds — knows no quantitative bounds. It has to use the same materials to build the imaginative structures that we use with our bodies and that our bodies are made of. But it can put them together in patterns which are beyond the limitations of what we call space and time. We must take bricks to build something, but we can build an infinite structure with those bricks. But we have to have bricks to start with. The imagination cannot entertain something that has not come into it from the outside. But once in there, then it can blow it up to any degree, or it can minimize it to any degree. But we have a very serious scientific vice, I think, of imputing our own limitations to the objective world.
A: You started out, earlier, saying you were worried about some particular characteristic of devoted physicists to place bounds on certain concepts, or at least to refuse to consider alternatives . . am I paraphrasing you correctly?
S: Yes. —will not even take a tentative hypothesis. They say, “All that’s been settled long ago.” (laughing)
A: It’s like — I don’t whether you’ll like this example — it’ s like a person who maintains a very firm religious belief, but wouldn’t dare consider someone else’s.
S: Or a scientific dogma, either. Like entropy.
A: Well, I suppose that a postulate can be — although a person doesn’t worship a postulate as some worship the Deity — you could say . . .
S: Well, theologians do; they think their articles of faith, and article by article they say that’s divinely set, frozen solid. Dogma.
A: But if a scientist is really worthy of the name, then his respect for a postulate is confined to the extent to which that postulate leads to useful predictions, or useful deductions. Once the postulate is shown to fail, then while it may be controversial and uncomfortable and all this — and it’s happened before — it doesn’t carry with it the stigma of deep fear or sin or whatever you want to call it. If a scientist is forced to repudiate one postulate and look for another, he doesn’t personally feel a great deal of guilt.
S: Certainly what you say is very true in modern times, since we began to question things. But answers anciently, and not very anciently at that, and even in some spheres of contemporary life, answers are absolute. Authority gives the answer. It must not be examined. And this postulate that you speak about which recent scientists have been so ready to question, and discard on the slightest indication of its invalidity, why, look at a postulate that’s, well, a thousand or two years old, and see how ready they are to discard it. When people who have been cherishing something for centuries, or for thousands of years, and it’s been taken up by authority and been enforced by authority for all that length of time, it’s a very difficult thing to get rid of any such premises as that.
A: Can you think of an example of such longstanding for which there is any evidence that it may not work — that there may be shortcomings in it?
S: We can find examples in the past, plenty.
A: Oh yes, in the past. These days there are so few fundamental principles, so far as I’m concerned, in the physical sciences, that — and of those I don’t know of any exceptions to them — that I can’t think of any examples. Like, you take the conservation principle. We’ve found no …well, I guess recently there was a generalization of the conservation principle to include the conservation of mass and energy. That is, if you write the law of conservation to include the reciprocity of energy and mass, it’s still valid. But just to write the conservation of energy is not necessarily complete.
S: Your equal sign between identifies them. It gives them equal authenticity.
A: But it’s only because the perturbations to physical theory have now sort of damped out since Einstein proposed this revolutionary concept.
S: Quantitatively, at least, you have the same thing on both sides of your equation. Qualitatively it may be a different organization. I’ll give you an example. You take a piece of work represented by a force through a distance, put that on one side of your equation. On the other side you put another piece of work, represented by a force through a distance. Now those have to be equal amounts or quantities of work, don’t they? But on one side you may have an enormous force through a short distance, and on the other you may have a minute force through a long distance. And you still have equality — quantitative equality. But not compositional equality. And you’ll find that all things, especially in the realm of art — all the arts, both the practical and the esthetic arts, all the creations there — are merely compositions. How things are composed. The quality of things. The things at which we attach value. The quality of things is a matter of how they are composed; it is not a matter of how large or how small they are.
A: In that equation of yours, I’m not sure I would care to say that they aren’t qualitatively the same — because work is a defined quantity that means a certain thing. And while certainly the composition of the number that quantitatively identifies the terms on each side — which would repudiate the equality if they weren’t numerically the same — nevertheless, qualitatively, looking at work done as a strain in a piece of solid material, produced by the lifting of a weight, or the movement of a force through a distance on a fulcrum . . .
S: Or a falling body . . .
A: Yes . . they are quantitatively very similar because they still imply the movement of a force through a distance. One of them may be on a microscopic scale, and one of them may be on a macroscopic scale.
S: But if you have the same amount of work on both sides, that work can be composed almost infinitely differently.
A: Oh yes, the composition. Well let’s say the composition in terms of
displacement in force, numerically speaking, may be quite different.
S: I’m thinking of the nature of the thing itself. A bit of work is done.
A force moves through a certain distance. On both sides of the equation, the
force can be an enormous force through a minute distance, on the one side,
and a minute force through an enormous distance on the other side. Now that
difference is not a quantitative difference — speaking now of work. It’s the
same amount of work on both sides. That’s what the signs mean between there.
But take it as a practical matter, and if you’re going to come in contact with
a body, a large body moving very slowly, you would probably have considerable
preference for that than a very small body moving very rapidly. (laughing)
I mean like a bullet.
A: Well I think that it would be more of a . . .
S: You’d only feel a mild pressure from a large body moving slowly, whereas in the other condition you’d have something that would pierce right through your body, perhaps.
A: Well looking at it from the point of view of human experience and
expressing psychological value judgments for things . . .
S: That is the world of value.
A: Oh — this is the way in which you are making the distinction.
S: And that is the world of value, isn’t it.
A: Oh yes, very definitely.
S: There are no values outside the human world.
(INTERRUPTION FOR SUPPER)
______________________________
A: The conservation energy is one — the first law of thermodynamics is the conservation of energy. And the second law of thermodynamics merely says . . Well, sit down, and I’ll . . .
S: I want to tell you what the other thing was.
A: All right, sir.
S: _________ one of the two things that I thought I might talk with you about, and the other was the implications of our free enterprise system for its further development.
A: That’s more like my question, that I wanted to talk to you about. So which shall we approach first?
S: I don’t like to think of a free enterprise system that has been built, it’s finished, and all we’ve got to do is to keep repeating it. It’s on the march. It’s going places it’s never been.
A: Oh I’m in complete sympathy with this point of view.
S: And I’m fascinated with the indications of what its future
possibilities are — beyond what it has already accomplished.
A: It’s of concern to some of my associates that my personal interest
sometimes, that is, my interest in the ultimate consequences and the
ultimate questions that would occur whenever we had no more worries about
constructing a proper society, but after we had one what would . . .
S: If you got it on a good working basis.
A: Yes, after we had constructed the so-called moral society, then, ask
myself questions and try to answer them in that perspective.
S: After you’ve got the automobile so it would run, then where do you
want to go with it? (laughing)
A: Yes. Some of my colleagues get a little impatient because maybe I
don’t devote enough of my energies to the immediate problem at hand of
constructing this moral society in the first place.
S: They’re not as imaginative as you are.
A: Well, I wouldn’t say that; I think that it’s a matter of priorities. I
can’t stop living, but I agree with them that this is more urgent. Nevertheless,
as a matter of personal satisfaction, I would prefer thinking about these
things.
S: I think that unless we do that . . . If we think of economics in a
pedestrian sort of a way — free-enterprise economics — as a thing that has
been achieved, accomplished, but is working under difficult conditions
owing to the impact of government upon it, and that our dream is that we
could get the government off its back so it wouldn’t be bothered with the
government any more, that is very pedestrian to me. Uninspiring.
A: I think we’ve merely started. I think that, first of all, we haven’t even
established — that is, established in the strict sense — a proper social
science. So how can we say that we know everything we want to know
about social organization and human action — interactions of human
beings and groups of human beings? I don’t think we’ve scratched. You’re
the first person I’ve met who I could truly say had given it a proper view,
who had looked at the characteristics of such a society . . .
S: As something that has been developing and is going somewhere?
A: . . . with a view to explaining how things would work when a society
was constructed as it ought to be. Like von Mises, for example, stops at the
point where he’s described the main features of a free market system —
and in terms of such devices as gold money which we have known before
and we know that it worked satisfactorily.
S: The same as barter did.
A: Yes. But von Mises never asks himself the question, is there something better? The trouble with that maybe is that some people will construe from such a question that von Mises may not be perfectly certain about what he’s talking about, if he asks himself that question. To me, it’s . . I know, for example, that von Mises’ ideas of the market economy are right, as far as they go . .
S: I agree with that, too.
A: . . and that a proper social science, after generations, will not repudiate the basic tenets of von Mises’ ideas. But von Mises’ ideas are not complete, and what will happen is the same sort of thing that happened when Einstein verified his relativity with respect to Newton’s mechanics. It did not repeal Newton’s mechanics at all. It did nor change the basic usefulness of Newtonian mechanics. But what it did do, is it placed limits on its validity and showed how it was a special case of a more general mechanics. I think the same thing could be said of what we now call classical economics.
S: We may say that because we have very much better steam engines nowadays, we don’t want to discredit James Watts.
A: Well of course not, and who wants to discredit James Watt? He was
first.
S: We don’t want to discredit von Mises . . .
A: No.
S: . . . even though we see that there’s a great deal to be accomplished yet.
A: Yes. Von Mises, from my own contact with him, is very difficult to talk to (with) about such questions. If you ask a question about money, his first reaction is a suspicion of your being what he calls, a “monetary quack” — or a “monetary crank,” I forget which term he used. But he is more or less unwilling to discuss concepts in terms other than those which he is accustomed to using.
S: He’s quite dogmatic. He’s got it laid down — in the proper words, proper thoughts, properly expressed! (laughing)
A: In a limited way. Not nearly so much as Ayn Rand though, I’ve found.
S: No.
A: Von Mises is easy to talk to in some respects, compared to Ayn Rand.
S: I tried to talk to her a little bit — oh, back about in the, somewhere
in the early thirties, I guess it was.
A: Really? Have you known her since then?
S: Well I didn’t know her but very briefly then — casually — and I’ve never seen her but once or twice since. Rather recently. I never had any . . .
A: Was she that way then?
S: Well I couldn’t say so definitely, I didn’t know her well enough. But I would infer that. She wasn’t a person who would discuss the merits of anything. She had her mind made up.
A: Well in some respects I have my mind made up too, and so do you. But this doesn’t mean that I can’t entertain a radically different view of things ..
S: That’s it.
A: . . . simply because, I’m confident that I understand what I’m talking about, and I have no fear that somebody else is going to confuse me. At least, I have enough confidence in myself to think that I’ll be able to judge a new idea. If I ever lose this, I think I’ll . . .
S: If there’s anything in this new idea, well then you might gain! (laughing)
A: Oh of course! I want to expose myself to all kinds of ideas.
S: And if it isn’t a sound idea, I’m well enough established not to be
knocked down by it. (laughing)
A: I had an interesting experience last Friday. I’m sort of an eccentric at the place where I work currently — at least I’m a non-conformist in the eyes of my colleagues there — and when somebody who they think is a crank, or another eccentric, comes in with some kind of a new idea, they don’t wish to seriously consider it, so they refer him to me. So I entertain all these. Some of them are crack-pots and some of them have good ideas, and I don’t like to take the chance that they won’t have a good idea, and I’ll be denied the benefit of hearing it.
S: You may miss something!
A: So, I don’t know if the man I talked to last Friday was a quack or not. Frankly, he didn’t present any evidence that I could appreciate; that is, he didn’t have what you might call an adequate amount of scientific information — I’ll put it that way — but I expect to follow up on it. He has a solid-state device that is just a lump of a kind of a plastic. There are two electrodes connected to the thing, and it generates power.
S: Send current from one electrode to the other?
A: The potential is established between the two electrodes, and this
potential can be used to produce a flow of current in an external circuit.
S: /Words not clear/
A: Well, this is what I think. I think that he has possibly a new type of electro-chemical device, like a storage battery.
S: It’s semi-solid?
A: It is solid. It’s an acrylic plastic or some sort.
S: These storage batteries, these flashlights, have semi-solids in them,
don’t they?
A: Yes. But they’re wet, most of them. This is a solid. This isn’t
unexpected, because GE has developed an ion-exchange membrane which
has all of the properties of — it’s a solid, it’s a plastic — and it has all
of the properties of an electrolyte. GE is merely using this as an electrolyte
for a fuel cell, where you put hydrogen and oxygen on each side of the membrane
constructed of this material, and you put a porous conductor on each side,
to form the electrodes, and then the hydrogen and oxygen react at one of the
electrodes and produce current. This is a classical electro-chemical fuel
cell.
S: Not very efficient.
A: They’re very efficient.
S: Are they?
A: Yes sir.
S: They’ll come into use then.
A: They are coming into use now. This would take some time, but you’re
going to see fairly soon, a company like Southern California Edison, having a brand new, entirely different competitor in the domestic power business. Southern California Gas Company will be their competitor. And the way in which the government has constrained the utilities business, it would have to be Southern California Gas Company. But there are imminent possibilities of handling a very efficient fuel cell, using natural gas and air, installed in your house like a water-heater — and with a net savings in capital to the supplier and in expense to the consumer.
S: Well does it pull in power from the outside, in the house?
A: No sir, just gas.
S: It brings in gas from the outside.
A: It just brings in gas, and generates power. It’s silent.
S: More power than what the gas itself would give by combustion?
A: Under some conditions, more efficient than a central power station
could burn the gas and use a heat engine as kind of a generator.
S: Of course that is pretty indirect, inefficient.
A: You see, a fuel cell doesn’t have a Second Law of Thermodynamics as a
limitation on its efficiency, as a heat engine does. The moment you go
through the intermediate step of converting a source of energy to heat, and
then to mechanical energy, you’re confronted with the Second-Law
limitation. And that brings me to the point I was going to mention. The two
postulates of thermodynamics are, the first, that you can’t get something for
nothing, and the second, you can’t even do that well. Now the first states
that you can’t . . you have to have an energy source, to generate power from
an engine. That’s the law of conservation of energy. Energy comes in, it’s
converted, and goes out in a different form. What comes in has got to go out.
Now the Second Law of Thermodynamics states that you can’t have an engine —
a heat engine — which can operate continuously on a single heat source. In
other words, it’s got to reject part of the heat that it got from its source,
to a sink. It can’t convert all of the energy that it gets from the source
to useful work. It’s got to reject part of it back to nature.
S: It can only dip part out of the stream.
A: That’s right. It can dip a lot out of the stream, but it has to put some back. And that that it puts back is unavailable for any useful work — at that datum. That’s the “Second law of thermodynamics. Thermodynamicists usually talk about perpetual motion machines of the first kind, and perpetual motion machines of the second kind, as having to do with these two laws. A perpetual motion machine of the first kind is an engine which does work without taking energy from any source.
S: Isn’t perpetual motion a misnomer?
A: Yes, that’s a misnomer. A perpetual motion machine of the second kind is one which takes energy from a single source and does work. Now there are thermodynamicists who have argued that there are all kinds of other principles, other postulates. Of course, thermodynamics is no exception. It’s one of the older of the mechanical sciences, and I imagine that hundreds of other postulates have been proposed. But no more than these two that I just gave you, in my opinion, are really needed. There is another one which was proposed just a couple of years ago, and that was the one which was the subject of my paper, called a state principle — in which . . .
S: Are these others derivative from the other two? Or derived?
A: It’s not an easy derivation, and I ran into difficulty myself trying to decide whether you had to make a new postulate . .well, I’ll see if I can’t explain it. A Professor Kline /Klein?/ at Stanford claims that you’re not entitled to write the equation of state, of a gas, that is, a mathematical equation, in terms of its intrinsic properties like temperature, pressure and volume, or energy, entropy and volume. The mere assumption that the gas has a state and it is described in terms of three properties is a postulate itself. This is Kline’s postulate. Kline postulates that to assume that the state of a gas can be described in terms of these three properties, constitutes a postulate. Now this is kind of quibbling, because first of all we have definitions of properties, and the definitions themselves are probably sufficient. The definitions of the physical quantities in terms of measurables is probably sufficient — sufficient to account for the so-called equation of state.
S: The postulates?
A: Without a postulate. Oh, you mean the definitions, are they postulates?
S: You don’t need to have the postulates between the definitions and the
equation?
A: I don’t. I don’t. I’m satisfied that you don’t need another postulate.
S: The simpler the better.
A: Yes. Because, definitions are not postulates. We have lots of definitions in thermodynamics. Pressure is a defined quantity. So is temperature. Temperature is much more abstract than pressure, though. Temperature is one of the most abstract quantities in any physical science.
S: Isn’t a definition related to an induction?
A: It is induction. It is inductive. It sure is. But I wouldn’t call it a postulate. I don’t think it conveys enough information.
S: Isn’t your induction a definition, as an induction? ___________ proceed from some foundation, some starting point?
A: I don’t even think you can have an induction before definition. Definitions are more primitive, than even a postulate.
S: ____________ , you’re right. It fits into Plato’s maxim, “He shall
be as a god to me who can rightly define, and divide.”
A: Well, I’m glad to be in agreement with Plato, for a change!
S: For a change, probably! (laughing) Not economically or politically. _____________________
A: No. But I think that definitions, and of course the way that this course that we’re teaching is constructed, this is the way that it’s done. Definitions are more primitive — that is, they come before you can proceed with the development of any postulatory . . .
S: Your algebra starts that way.
A: Yes. Well, doesn’t also geometry?
S: I think I’m thinking of geometry, really.
A: Well, the theory of numbers is little more than definitions and some simple ___________, isn’t that correct?
S: I imagine so. I’m not authority, though. (laughing) But I’m fascinated with the part that numbers, magnitudes based on discontinuities, are the important things we can manipulate rationally. If your magnitude is not based on a discontinuity, let us say on a unit, then it has no rational content, because it cannot be compared in terms of numbers, with another magnitude.
A: Well I’m aware of your idea on time as being also discontinuous, that
is, there is no continuity in time either. Well let’s say, time is not a
continuum. And if that’s so, if time is not a continuum either, then I can’t
think of anything that is, in nature.
S: Time is manifested in motion — and motion is not a continuum. It
remains for us now to consider whether mass is a continuum or not.
A: Mass isn’t.
S: I think not.
A: Mass is made of particles. I mean, any substance can be broken downinto
particles in smaller and smaller units.
S: In these three elements of action, these three elements of any quantity
of work, (we) have units.
A: Yes, they have fundamental units.
S: Discontinuity means units.
A: Yes, but the continuity, let’s say the continuum physics, while it may not be microscopically correct, it is physically useful.
S: The same as statistical conclusions are useful.
A: Yes. I guess you’d use statistics to obtain continuity where there isn’t any.
S: Yes, artificial continuity. I’m very happy to hear you say that, because I was wondering how much confirmation I could find from people who are better versed than I on this matter of continuity.
A: I haven’t thought very much about whether there’s continuity in time, but I know that in a sense, one of your ideas on this is satisfying to me, and that is, time, as far as human sensibilities are concerned, is made up of discrete intervals, and there’s no continuity as far as humans measure time. So this has made me suspicious that there may not be any real continuity except statistically, for time also.
S: It manifests itself to our sensory system as a discontinuity.
A: Yes. That doesn’t mean that it isn’t continuous, but it makes me
suspicious.
S: That means for practical purposes, as for physical purposes — even if it may
not be so for metaphysical purposes. ‘For physical purposes at least, and for physical and practical and objective purposes, time is discontinuous.
A: Yes.
S: That clock has to tick.
A: Now, epistemologically, is it useful to talk about time in a metaphysical sense,
at the same time you talk about time in a physical sense?
S: Well if you’re talking about metaphysical phenomena — metaphenomena or
__________, or psychic phenomena of any kind, then you can talk about continuum or whatever you like. But we know that the environment with which our physical part, our soma, is related, is discontinuous. If it were not, we’d have no way to mark time or to appreciate time or, to experience time. We can only experience time by reason of its discontinuity.
A: Yes, because at any instant, I don’t observe any motion in the hands of my watch. It’s only when it moves from one number to the next that I perceive the movement of time.
S: Except these clocks which I notice . . those large clocks, the hand moves every second. They stand still between. Have you noticed that? (laughing)
A: No, but I think if you really wanted to get right down to it, so do these hands. They don’t really move continuously. I think if you put a very sensitive dial indicator on, say, the hour hand of this watch, you’d find that it moved in a jerky way itself.
S: But let’s notice some of the corollaries, if I may call them such — if we are going to assume, at least, that time is discontinuous and that motion, which marks time, is also discontinuous, and that mass, which undergoes motion and from which motion proceeds, is discontinuous, then we are assuming the three fundamental, absolute units in the objective world.
A: Would you repeat that?
S: We are assuming then that ___________________ mass, motion and time, are discontinuous — and come in discrete quantities.
A: Yes, they all three do.
S: Then, we must either say that there are absolute units in those three fields, or else that there is a field of no discontinuity. The moment you abandon the basic unit, you have assumed that there is a field — of mass, let us say, that is discontinuous.
A: Is the implication that, if there is a discontinuity, there is a more fundamental unit?
S: Yes, that there is a fundamental unit. Not more fundamenta1 — like something being more unique! (laughing)
A: Oh. That there may be something fundamental which relates all three of these.
S: No, I think these three are related to each other. We know in fact they are, as a matter of practice. But looking at the nature of the three aspects of an event, the mass aspect, motion aspect and the time aspect, and assuming that below a certain magnitude, we’ll say, take any one, take the mass, below a certain unit of mass, that there is no more divisibility, no more discontinuity. Then we have two kinds of a cosmos. Below a certain point it’s continuous, and above a certain point, it’s discontinuous.
A: Well let’s see. It’s easier to talk about mass than it is the others, as far
as I’m concerned. Below a certain point, you have to stop talking about mass and
start talking about energy.
S: Well then you’ve mixed in your motion and time, if you make energy out of it.
A certain amount of work (per) unit of time . . .
A: Okay then let’s forget it; this more or less proves the interrelationship of
mass, motion and time.
S: Oh yes, I’m taking that for granted. I’m just considering mass alone for
the moment.
A: Okay. Well you get to the point just before you have to start talking about units of energy rather than mass, and that is at the atomic level.
S: Whatever it may be.
A: Well, the nuclear level, where you have particles of mass approximately equal
to the mass of a proton.
S: ________________ bring in any conception that we didn’t absolutely have to have. (laughing)
A: Well, you get to the point where there are small particles of mass — having masses.
S: But what I want to point out is that there has to be an absolute minimum unit of mass, or else there’s a quantity at which there is no discontinuity.
A: There’s still discontinuity here, as far as I’m concerned.
S: Yes. Well now if you have discontinuity, you’ve got to have units. And to have smaller units than a certain unit, you would have to have a unit less than which will not integrate with motion and time. The three have got to come together to make an event, to make an item of work, or action. You’ve got to have both force, and motion, to get work, or action — to get anything that can be experienced. And shall we say that there is no unit of mass so small that it would not combine with a unit of motion?
A: (Long pause, dubiously) No . .
S: Then that’s the least unit.
A: That unit of mass which . . .
S: . . . less than which will not combine with motion.
A: A unit of mass so small, that at any velocity, its energy is zero. Is that right?
S: It wouldn’t assume any velocity. It wouldn’t take on any velocity.
A: Oh! But I don’t know — you can talk about velocity, as an abstraction.
S: Well of course every ratio is an abstraction, and velocity isn’t anything but a ratio. It has no energy; it’s a relationship between two numbers.
A: Now, it’s more physically meaningful to me to talk about energy — say kinetic energy — as being the product of mass times the velocity squared . . .
S: Well let me raise a question here. I’m rather shy of using the term energy because it seems to me we use it in two senses. we talk about buying and selling energy, you know, and we also talk about energy as a rate of work.
A: No — energy isn’t the rate of work, that’s power.
S: Well, then, let’s call it power then. We can also call it power. But power sounds to me like potential — something that’s capable of doing something. Something like potential energy of an _______________.
A: No, until the energy is actually producing some effect, it still is just energy. As soon as it begins to do work at a certain rate, then it becomes power, strictly speaking. I mean, this is using the definitions of . . .
S: We’re drawing a distinction between a rate of energy and a quantity of energy.
A: Yes, we’re making that distinction.
S: Now let’s see what the figures are. If we take — shall we use the English measure? Take a pound.
A: All right.
S: And it moves through one unit of motion, called a foot.
A: If we’re taking a pound of mass and we’re going to use English units, we have to be careful as to whether we’re talking about pounds of mass or pounds of force.
S: Well we use the same unit in our measuring, don’t we?
A: No, it isn’t the same unit. That’s what’s wrong with using the British
system.
S: Force is measured in pounds, is it not, and mass is measured in pounds,
is it not?
A: Yes, but they’re different units.
S: You mean a difference in gravity and ____________ ?
A: One pound-force is equal to one pound of mass accelerated at a rate of 52.2
feet per second. Now the ratio which defines that force which produces one foot per
second per second acceleration on one pound of mass, is another unit called poundal.
It’s a different unit. A one-pound mass accelerated at one foot per second squared
. . .
S: Much as a dyne is different from an erg, isn’t it?
A: Yes. Well . . no.
S: A dyne is different from a gram.
A: No, a dyne and an erg are different concepts.
S: A dyne and a gram, I’m thinking of.
A: Yes. The British have corrupted the metric system also. There’s a metric
gravitational system and the absolute system. Now you don’t get into trouble using
absolute system with metrics, because you can talk about forces in terms of dynes,
and masses in terms of grams, and there’s never any confusion, because you don’t
use the name to apply to different concepts. But in the British system, you can have
a pound of mass and a pound of force, and they’re different — the same name, but
different concepts. And this is a grievous thing to a lot of engineers. I used to
have trouble with it myself until I thought about it and ____________
S: In the CGS system you don’t have that confusion, do you?
A: No. None at all.
S: Well sticking to the CGS system — I call it GCS myself, for what I think is good reason, but don’t need to go into that now. It doesn’t matter, does it.
A: No, it doesn’t.
S: I feel that the gram is the primary experience, that we have to feel something
like weight or force or pressure or inertia, before we can consider motion, and that
we have to consider motion before we can consider time. I think there is a natural
order in which they come into our consciousness, or our sense organs.
A: If you’re going to try to apply these concepts to human experience, isn’t what
we actually experience, motion?
S: Well, motion of something.
A: Motion of something. Something discrete.
S: Of something that moves. (laughing)
A: Yes. If everything else is moving at the same rate we are, we don’t
experience motion even.
S: That something seems to be a prerequisite. A prerequisite to motion is something
to move, isn’t it.
A: Yes. And I guess more specifically, relative motion.
S: Yes, as all motion is.
A: Yes . . That’s right. But things have to be moving in relation to us before we sense an event.
S: Yes, or between some parts of us. We can feel our heart moving and feel our
respiration, we can feel our thumb moving towards or away from our fingers. And yet
we always have to have something to move before we get motion.
A: But the different senses experience events differently, it seems to me.
S: Because they’re different senses.
A: Yes, the experience we get from our eyes, is motion, discrete motion
— something moving relative to us from one corner to the next.
S: Yes.
A: The experience we get from our feel . . our. . .
S: Sense of touch, though . . .
A: . . our sense of touch, is pressure, or impact.
S: But you feel the original sense on your body — you feel a motion from here to
here, from your knee to your elbow, or your knee to your thigh, or one side of your
face to another.
A: Maybe this is revealing: If a pressure is brought to bear on a spot of the body
for a long period of time, you get to the point where you don’t sense it anymore.
You accommodate to it. There is a point before that, though, that you still sense
it; so you can say that you sense pressure, or force, so long as you don’t accommodate
to it. Therefore, maybe what you actually sense is not the force, but a sort of an
impact, the more . . Let’s see. We get into that time response business that we were
talking about once before, you know — a human being has a “band width,” so to speak.
You know this particular concept?
S: No.
A: Of a “band width?”
S: No.
A: A human being has a certain frequency response. He responds to a certain spectrum of frequencies between . . .
S: /Not audible/
A: At a low enough frequency he doesn’t respond to it at all. Like, most people don’t respond to frequencies common in the economic realm which are, like, a generation or so. They don’t respond to these frequencies.
S: Or the gastronomic frequencies.
S: Any low frequencies, they don’t . . .
/INTERRUPTION TO CHANGE TAPE/
______________________________
S: Let’s go back a little bit, . .
A: All right.
S: . . . and try not to introduce anything except what we have to introduce. I think what I introduce! (laughing)
A: All right.
S: I’m trying to take that which is least complex at each step. And the first thing I want to introduce is that there is such a thing as — whatever it is that we measure by a gram, and some call it inertia, some call it force, some call it mass. But whatever it is, in dealing quantitatively, if we use the same measurement — that is, the same _____________ or units, whatever it is, and the idea is that there is a basic unit, I mean in the sense that it’s indivisible and that it is unanalyzable of course . . and that it has to be that big in order to generate motion.
A: It has to be that big, to generate motion.
S: Yes. If it were smaller than that, it wouldn’t manifest motion, it wouldn’t generate motion. No motion would come out of it. I just want to take that tentatively for the time being. Don’t let’s question whether it’s demonstrable.
A: I want to be sure I understand what you mean by motion, that’s all. You mean by motion that it can take on a velocity?
S: Well we come to that. We find that motion always generates time. Or rather, time always proceeds out of motion. Just as mass generates motion.
A: Oh, okay. Below a certain point, a mass no longer is a mass which can be identified with a change of position. . .No — that starts to get into an argument.
S: Of course it’s motion if it’s in the mass of some magnitude that might have motion like a spinning top, without any change in its over-all position but change over the position of all its parts with respect to its environment.
A: You don’t get very far in this before you find yourself immersed in other fundamental quantities.
S: Well let’s submit to that if it’s necessary.
A: All right.
S: But don’t let’s do it unnecessarily.
A: I’m beginning to wonder if it isn’t necessary right off the bat.
S: Well, if it is, that necessity should make itself manifest. As a necessity, and not as something we import voluntarily.
A: Because if you want to define the limits on mass, and you’re unable to do this without introducing one of the other fundamental concepts, this suggests that …
S: We’re just using the imagination now, and the imagination can
disregard other things that go with mass.
A: Well you’re talking about motion, and I asked, what is it.
S: Well, having assumed whatever it is that we commonly think of as mass, we immediately consider it as having motion. And the fact is, when we speak of a pound mass, we always mean, for practical purposes, that that pound’s going to be repeated every time you have a unit of motion. As soon as you have mass and motion combined, then you repeat the mass every time you repeat the motion unit. That’s why you multiply the number of pounds by the number of feet, or the number of grams by the number of centimeters. Here is a quantity of motion. A quantity of motion is the number of centimeters. We’re multiplying the quantity of mass by the quantity of motion.
A: Okay . . so the term motion here is used in the sense of a displacement.
S: Yes.
A: It doesn’t invoke the other basic unit, namely time.
S: Well that appears in its proper sequence. First we will say we have motion in the sense of displacement, and the thing that moves we call, say, ten centimeters /grams?/. Well that means it’s ten centimeters /grams?/every time you have a unit of motion. So if you have ten units of motion, you multiply the ten by the ten to get the total mass-motion content, which is work. Isn’t that right? That’s the same as force times distance. Mathematically the same thing.
A: Well, not necessarily. If you moved ten units of mass ten centimeters on a frictionless plane, and took an infinite amount of time to do this, there wouldn’t be any work involved, because there would be no force. But not necessarily.
S: Right. we’ve introduced an infinity, which of course doesn’t come
within the range or the purview of our experiences.
A: No . . so the implication . . okay. Physically, you can’t have this without some kind of a force, so there would be work involved here. But is it synonymous, if you find that a mass . . .
S: I’m asking you to just give consideration to these questions, and not inquire into their validity for the moment. (laughing)
A: All right, okay. So we have a concept of mass, which is . . .
S: And when we say so many units of mass, we mean that as it enters into our experience, it has to take on the form of motion, and that these numbered units of mass must be so many units for each unit of motion. So that makes a mass or force times a distance. Which we call work.
A: All right, so you’re asking me to consider a concept wherein wherever a mass of so many units, in terms of gram, is found to be displaced from one position to another — now so many units of displacement in centimeters …
S: And you repeat that mass every time you have a new unit of displacement .
A: Yes . . and we call the combination work.
S: Yes. Now we further find that as we approach (in our imagination) an objective event which we can experience . . . We can’t experience this, because we can’t experience work as such without time. Time has to come into it, and of course we haven’t integrated the three together to make something that we can experience. we can’t experience it without time. So this amount of work has to be done during so many units of time. And so if there are so many units of time, we multiply this amount of work by so many units, to get the quantity of work done in the quantity of time.
A: And you call this . .
S: We call that the total of the work. We try and measure how much work there is. The mass times the units of motion gives the quantity of work, but we don’t know now long that took. If we say it took one second, and then it continued to operate through several more seconds, we must multiply it by the number of seconds of duration that this event occupies.
A: The longer it takes, the more you got?
S: Yes.
A: That’s curious.
S: Because your unit of motion is tied to a unit of time. And so if you have two units of time, you have twice as much work.
A: This is exactly opposite from the way . . .
S: Now you give me an opposite conception and see it work. (laughing)
A: I’m just making a comparison; you don’t want me to do that yet. Okay. So we have a concept of total work, which is the quantitative work that we previously defined . . .
S: We can say that mass times motion is work. Gram times centimeter is work. And that if that amount occupies one unit of time, that that is a rate of work. If it occupies two units of time . . I mean that if it continues through two, I don’t mean that if you split it up.
A: Oh! Okay . .
S: It continues. Durational time, I’m talking about.
S: Okay now, okay.
S: Not time in the sense of its division, dividing it up.
A: During each period, each one of these units of time, it does the same quantitative amount of work, then integrating over this period gives you the total amount of work.
S: And then if you have two units of time, there will be twice as much work. Two units of duration. I sometimes use the expression, time as frequency, and time as duration — durational time.
A: Perfectly satisfactory.
S: Well, don’t commit yourself too much. We’re just looking at it anyhow, we’re not trying to evaluate it. Giving it what Emerson called, “intelligent consideration.” We’re not either denying it or accepting it. (laughing)
A: I think what I mean by that is that I am following.
S: So we now find that if we have a quantity of work being done, and we want to analyze it into its constituents, do a quantitative analysis of it, we’ll call it . . let’s say ten grams through ten centimeters per second, during ten seconds. So many grains per centimeter, and so many centimeters per unit, during ten seconds. Then we have a thousand units of work in the whole combination. Because we have ten grams of force, or mass, for each unit of motion, and we have ten units of motion, then we have a hundred gram-centimeter units
which are work units, aren’t they, gram-centimeter units? Work units?
A: All right, okay. And each one of these units of work . . .
S: And this is per each unit of time. So then if we have ten units of time, we’ll have an over-all quantity of work represented by one thousand work units.
A: All right.
S: Now we’re going to keep that one thousand, because we’re talking about a certain quantity of work — just as I talked about a certain quantity of life-years in my book. We’re not going to change that quantity, although we may change the elements which compose it.
A: The proportions of the elements . .
S: As we change one, we must make a corresponding reciprocal change in the other, in order that we shouldn’t change our over-all quantity of work, which is a thousand.
So then let us make it, instead of ten units of mass, let’s make it one unit of mass, and one hundred units of motion, per unit of time. And this, by ten units of time, will make a thousand units of work, the same as before, won’t it?
A: Umhm.
S: Except that the composition between our first two elements, instead of being
10 to 10, is 1 to 100 — and any other proportions we want to make up that comes
to a hundred. Factor one hundred as much as you like. Now whatever be the composition
of work done per unit of time, whatever the composition be, just so it amounts to
a hundred units of work per unit of work /time?/ then if the units of time are ten,
we’ll still have a thousand units of in the whole event which we’ve been analyzing.
Now we took a thousand units to begin with, and we’ve analyzed it into two ways
— one into ten times ten times ten, and the other into one by one hundred by ten.
And we can go on making any number of different analyses of it, showing that a given
quantity of work represented by one hundred units of work can have a tremendous
variety of composition without having any change of dimension. Yet its interior
dimensions are being changed all the time — what we call its compositional
dimensions.
A: You might call this the quality of the work.
S: I was about to say . . the quality of the work. Because we experience it
differently.
A: I’ll say.
S: And that’s why it’s quality.
A: We do in physics too.
S: Yes. Well, quality always means that some evaluation _______________. We evaluate it differently according to how it’s composed. So that identifies composition with quality. You took the words out of my mouth.
A: I’m sorry.
S: Oh no, I wanted you to get it, and you got it ahead of time. (laughing) When
I say “get it,” I don’t mean accept it — Just to look at it.
A: I think I see what you’re getting at now. You’re getting at several basic
. . well they’re not so basic, but they are still fundamental considerations in
thermodynamics. And they are not approached from this point of view, so that they
are . . .
S: I’m not sophisticated enough to know all of the technical aspects of the
thing.
A: But there are concepts of availability, like you could take a certain fixed
Quantity of energy — however you’re calling it work — and of this quantity, how
much work can you get out of it in a heat engine. Well that depends on what level
of energy this energy is in. Now the level of temperature that this energy is existing
at, may be called the quality of it. Now this is my term. I haven’t seen this anywhere
else.
S: I think it may match out all right, but I’m a little bit confused about
it. Because I’m trying to exclude all of those further considerations that
this doesn’t lead us into.
A: Okay, don’t let me distract you. Let me try and follow yours.
S: If we have them, I want to grow up to them. I don’t want to have to come
down and oppose them _________ my basic pattern.
A: All right, I’ll try not to interrupt you.
S: (laughing) I want to note some of the consequences, having it clearly fixed in our mind now that a hundred /thousand?/ units of work, made up of a composition of mass and motion multiplied by the durational time, the number of time units through which it extends, to give the magnitude of the whole event. Having that clear in mind, then it is susceptible to us factoring it — a change of ratio between the first two — which affects its quality but does not affect its quantity. I think that is fundamental . . could be thought of as fundamental . . in our whole objective world, perhaps giving us a little light on what we mean by a quantitative or a qualitative change. Then remembering that we have decided that we are dealing with a fundamental unit of mass, less than which would not enter into a quantity of work, less than which would not take on motion — which is requisite that there be motion — having done that, this can’t possibly be any smaller. And that means, then, that the hundred . . one times a hundred, is it not . . that the hundred units of motion is the largest possible hundred units of motion per unit of time. Since the unit of mass can’t get any smaller, then the hundred units of motion must be the highest amount of motion that you could have per unit of time.
A: Why? You can’t have fractional mass?
S: We’ve said it’s indivisible, that it’s to be taken as an absolute unit of
mass. An indivisible unit of mass.
A: Okay, whatever these units are..
S: They’re the natural minimum units.
A: One of these is . .
S: Measured in a gram for convenience.
A: Okay, supposing the gram is the elemental . .
S: All right, or we can just as well say some fraction of a gram could
be the elemental quantity. And this means that there are basic units in
nature.
A: Okay.
S: So on the basis of that, in that particular composition, the number of motion
units per unit of time would be as high as it could ever get. But if you could cut
down on your mass unit, smaller, you’d get more motion units per unit of time,
wouldn’t you.
A: Uh huh.
S: Well on that simple hypothesis, and I think it seems oversimplified to you,
probably . .
A: No . .
S: At any rate, on that simple hypothesis, the velocity of light is a derived
consequence, a corollary of the analysis of the quantity of work. In like manner,
let us cut down the durational time units to one. And then we have, whatever the
product is of the first two, which may be one times a hundred or a hundred times
one, or ten times ten, if that remains a hundred, but when we cut down the time unit
from ten to one, that has to become a thousand. And now the quantity of work done
per unit of time is a thousand.
A: And you’re going to leave that fixed.
S: Well how could it be any greater?
A: The total amount of work done in ten units of time was a thousand.
S: Yes.
A: And that’s going to remain fixed.
S: But now that we have reduced the number of units of time from ten to one,
we must increase the number of units of work from one hundred to one thousand.
A: But if you have a minimum mass, it can’t be done.
S: Well either way, let the mass be what it will, and the motion be what it
will, if it’s a hundred — ten by ten, or one by a hundred, or a hundred by one
— let it be what it will, then if you reduce your durational time unit, the
number of repetitions of your time unit, from ten to one, then in order to preserve
your thousand, not to change your over-all magnitude, you must now have a thousand
units of work in one unit of time. And unless you can make a unit of time less
than one, that’s the highest possible rate of work — the highest quantity of
work per unit of time which is rated to time. And so . . .
A: Where one unit of time is the smallest increment of time you can have.
S: Yes. You couldn’t split the unit. Just as we can’t split the quantum units, they say. Now that gives us, then, something resembling an atomic explosion, because you couldn’t have any greater quantity of work done in a unit of time, than that, without increasing your total quantity. We’ve had two transformations within a given quantity of work, which was a thousand — made up of so many units of mass times so many units of motion per unit of time, and so many units of time. We’ve switched them around. The first switch made it appear that the motion units per unit of time couldn’t be any greater than that, unless we diminished the mass. And we’ve got the mass already at its minimum. The other is, suppose we diminish the duration time. Then we’ll have to have ten times as much work done per unit of time in order to have it done in one unit of time, instead of ten.
A: But once you reach the maximum velocity, the maximum motion per unit of
time, the only way you can increase the energy under these conditions is to
increase the mass. You’ve got the minimum time increment, you’ve got the
maximum motion increment, so then the only way you can increase the energy is
to increase the mass.
S: The first two terms represent mass times motion, doesn’t it, and that is fixed at a hundred. Although it may be in different factored . . .
A: Okay.
S: That’s fixed at a hundred. And that means that your time units must be ten, if you’re going to preserve the original quantity of work that we started out to examine. And we’re not going to change our quantity when we’re in the midst of an analysis, are we.
A: No.
S: So we’re going to keep that thousand firm out there. Well that calls for . . . . so wherever your mass times motion is a hundred, you’ve got to have ten out there, in that third term. But now if you reduce that third term to one, then you’ve got to have a thousand in the first two terms.
A: Right — which brings no constraint over the composition.
S: Now since you can’t reduce it any further, by definition — it’s the minimal unit of time — therefore you can’t increase the quantity of work done per unit of time. You have the highest possible rate of energy, or rate of action — or rate of work, I’d better call it to avoid confusion of terms. So there gives us something to indicate how, with a given quantity of work represented by a thousand, we can have no more than a certain amount of velocity, and no less than a certain rate of work.
A: Uhhuh.
S: And that seems to correspond with what we call velocity of light on the
one hand, and with what we call the highest possible energy of explosion or
disintegration . . And notice when that energy takes place, that last one, your
mass element is at its minimum, and if it’s one, one can be considered as
having no effect on the multiplication. We can consider it as non-existent, for
mathematical purposes. Because the factor of one doesn’t change the
product. So then we account for mass turning into energy, or into work, as I
prefer to call it.
A: Mass-energy__________________________
S: Because when mass gets at its minimum, it can only be as a factor of one, and one doesn’t multiply anything. And that may be another way of looking at the famous idea of converting mass into energy.
A: The equivalence of matter and energy.
S: Equivalence. Yes. And so there’s a third possibility, too. There’s a
possibility that the amount of motion can be reduced to a single unit. I haven’t
mentioned that before. That means that there would have to be ten times as
much mass, doesn’t it, other things being alike, and so if your motion is at a
single unit, then your mass is at its highest ratio, of mass per unit of motion,
and your motion is at its lowest possible level. Which would be something
corresponding to what we call absolute zero. Though it’s not absolute,
because it’s still a quantity. (laughing) But it’s a quantity which is only one
unit and therefore it doesn’t multiply anything. So we have those three
physical phenomena rather as corollaries to the basic conception of a
thousand units of work made up of ten units of mass per each unit of motion,
and ten units of mass-motion per each unit of time, through ten units of
durational time. And taking that as the basic event, or event, or hypothesis,
that hypothesis contains within itself these three different aspects of action.
A: You have shown, how you can derive the concept of a maximum velocity,
a maximum rate of energy release, as in annihilation of an atom, and the
minimum motion, equivalent to absolute zero.
S: Minimum motion per unit of time.
A: Per unit of time, which is equivalent to absolute zero — and as a matter of fact, has a physical analogy. This is the point at which molecular motion, as they call it, ceases. It really doesn’t. But there is a minimum amount of molecular activity at a point called absolute zero, and on the thermodynamic scale of temperature . . .
S: But I would say it most likely shouldn’t be thought of as absolute,
because it contains one unit of motion. And absolute zero means no motion at
all.
A: Well it is a misnomer, because at that point there is no possibility of doing any thermal work, but there is still matter, there are still other forms of energy there.
S: There’s still a unit of motion there.
A: There’s still a unit of motion.
S: And that is probably why we can only approach the absolute asymptotically. We can get where there really is a minimum there. And besides, the concept of a zero is something that our senses refuse to recognize. Our imagination entertains it.
A: Just like . . it’s probably no more difficult to conceive of infinity than
it is of zero.
S: Just the same.
A: It’s the same thing.
S: We can conceive of both of them with perfect ease. But our senses
refuse to recognize either one.
A: Ah, yes. Perceive, I should say.
S: So our sensory experience, which then we call our physical, or objective
experience, runs on some octave, as it were — on some scale between zero
and infinity, both of which are incapable of being experienced objectively.
A: I should have said “perceive,” not “conceive.” We can conceive of it.
S: Yes, oh yes. And our sensory system is so constructed that that octave has appreciably expanded in past time. It probably can expand much more.
A: But it can only approach these things.
S: It can never reach either of these; only the mind can reach the absolute.
We can’t make it towards zero or towards infinity. And that gives us our place
in nature, man’s place in nature. But I wanted to present that little formula,
that little hypothesis of a thousand units of work being capable of manifesting
itself in several different varieties within certain limits. And I gave you the
three different possible limits, corresponding with the three different kinds of
experiences that we have had.
A: Excuse me. (To Evie) Are you going to bed now?
EV: Yes, sir.
A: Well say goodnight, to Mrs. Manning, to Mr. Heath. (Sound of a kiss)
S: (Affectionate laughing)
A: She’s the affectionate one. The other one is shy.
S: One of mine was like that, the middle one. Good night, young lady, good night. (Hugging and affection) She’s a very sweet young lady.
A: Can I have one too? (Loud kiss) Good night.
EV: Good night.
A: (To Rosamina) You too? Good night, Rosie. (Loud kiss)
S: She’s going to give me one too, no doubt. (To Rosie) Give me one too? (Hugging) Ummm, that’s a good girl!
A: She’s going to be my musical artist. And I think Evie’s going to be my graphical artist.
S: Oh . . Wonderful!
A: She’s very talented.
S: It will be so nice they can complement each other.
A: Yes.
S: They won’t be rivals.
A: Oh, they’re rivals already!
S: (Laughing) In those respects — if one is gifted in sight and the other in sound, then they’ll be complements rather than rivals.
A: They get along very harmoniously, actually. They have common . . it’s easy to observe the natural phenomenon of property interacting between kids.
S: Yes.
A: Whatever they have, it’s theirs, and it’s very valuable to them, and they don’t like to share things. They don’t come by this act of sharing naturally.
S: But that’s not a social phenomenon, as you know, because they don’t relate themselves to one another. They exclude themselves from one another by this process.
A: They’re too young to..
S: As soon as they use this property as capital, use it in the service of others, then they’re integrating their lives with other lives. The social concept of property is that which may be used in the service of others. The animal concept of property is that which may be withdrawn from the advantage of others. Quite the reverse idea. And we are very slowly coming to understanding that, in society, capital is not something you use yourself or enjoy yourself. Capital is something which you make other people enjoy.
A: Yes sir.
S: ________ the reverse. That’s a little example of the things I’ve
thought to bring out whenever I have the opportunity, inherent in our capitalist system, the free enterprise system.
A: Do you want to give exposition to these concepts again?
S: Yes . . (laughing)
A: Because this is one of the reasons I wanted this on tape; I wanted to listen to this again. I hope it comes out good. Because…
/Some discussion with Mrs. Manning
whether the tape is recording properly/
S: I’m inclined to think we got past that point which was brought up by the children being here and having property among themselves . . .
A: Well now does this bring us to the next point?
S: No, that was a digression. It was taking us away from it.
A: That was a digression. We want to continue with the development of the fundamental units.
S: I laid down a hypothesis that there were three fundamental units, and just tentatively and not trying to support it at once, although I have in mind that it can be supported. And seeing that we don’t need any conception but the conception of the three basic units, of different kinds, which are necessary to be unified or integrated to bring about an event which we can experience through our senses.
A: Measurable quantities.
S: Yes. Of course they’re imaginative, and they’re only objective when they come into this integration which we call a given quantity of work.
A: Yes. That’s the part that’s difficult.
S: Yes. The rest of it is metaphysical.
A: Or I should say, it’s difficult to avoid that part.
S: Yes, the premise of the three units is a metaphysical premise. Because unless they’re combined . . any one or two of them, without the third, is outside the range of the physical sensorium. (laughing) It only comes into the range of physical experience, of sensory experience when the three are there in some proportion. And if they come there in different proportions, they have a different effect upon our sensory system and therefore we evaluate them differently. So the quality of the event depends not upon its magnitude, but upon its composition. Now this is a basic point of view which, if it is valid and can be supported, gives us a much more fundamental understanding.
A: Well, the interesting thing about this development is the introduction
of this concept of quality, which you don’t get by considering these
things in the conventional way of physics, where they’re usually
interrelated from the beginning. You don’t talk about work except
in terms of mass, motion and time from the beginning. Energy, or
rather power, as you’re using energy per unit time, is all three at
once. You get to energy very quickly, and they’re already integrated
by the time you start talking about . . .
S: When you pay your bill to the power company, you pay for this product.
of mass, motion and time. In the beginning.
A: Durational time.
S: Yes.
S: Not how many times within a unit of time, how many repetitions . . but how many units of time are involved in the event.
/Interruption — David and baby Alvin/
S: Oh how do you do, young man!
David: We’ve been very pleased to meet you. We’re glad you came over.
S: Well, you’re just like me. I’m pleased too.
David: Thanks.
S: We’re all pleased. I hope you have a nice sleep, and happy dreams.
David: Thank you, and you too. I hope you come again. |
A: Good night, boys. |
Boys: Good night.
S: I’ve now mentioned three extremes. I’ve said nothing about the intermediate. When we realize that, inasmuch as these physical units are exceedingly small, there must be a tremendous variety. You could have two times fifty, or anything that would make up a hundred — four times twenty-five, and have something in proportion . . you would have a set of three different kinds of events, and all within the same magnitude.
A: And there’s nothing that says that these units have to be: integral; you can have fractional units also.
S: No, because by hypothesis these units of mass, motion and time are at their minimum.
A: But anything above that, you can have one and a half . . .
S: But multiples, yes. Multiples, but not fractions. Just as with the quantum, you can have multiples, but not fractions. (laughing)
A: Okay.
S: So I’ve found at a lower level there — or at least I’ve assumed at a lower level — units in that respect like the quantum unit. That while you can have multiples, you can’t have fractions. And there is a fair inference, too, a fair assumption, that if the quantum unit itself has those characteristics, its ingredients might be the same. An inference _______ I don’t want to say conclusively ___________ inference. However, it develops that way because the hypothesis is that these units are at their minimum. And being at their minimum, they can’t be fractioned.
A: So you can only have integral . . any number of things in terms of quanta, as energy.
S: Yes.
A: Because the quantum is indivisible.
S: Now let us suppose this thousand represents not a thousand units of work —
that’s what I’ve been calling it, isn’t it, a thousand units of work — but only so
much work as is represented by an integration of one unit of motion times one unit
of time divided by h. Now h is a fraction. . . Multiplied by h . . .divided by h
would be multiplied by the reciprocal of h, then it avoids confusing it. Multiply
by a fraction, you think of dividing by the whole number.
A: Yes.
S: Then transforming this thousand, which aspect has a rather large quantity, to the very small product, a small quantity, we find that we can find a high degree of composition within the quantum itself.
A: h is a factor . . .
S: Let us take an erg second, which is a gram, one gram per unit of motion times
one unit of motion per unit of time, during one unit of time. That’s an erg
second . . that’s an erg!
A: Analogous to it.
S: Well it’s a small-scale erg, and authorities all tell us that a quantum of action
is a certain definite fraction of an erg. That’s stated flatly and diagrammed and
everything else, again and again. So if a quantum of action is a small fraction of
an erg, then all we have to do is to take an erg at its one unit of mass times one
unit of motion times one unit of time and multiply it by h, which means we’re dividing
it by a very large number . . .
A: Unhuh.
S: We reduce it to a magnitude which transforms an erg into a quantum. If they’re right, and I’m taking their word for it, that a quantum is a definite, but an exceedingly small fraction of an erg.
A: There’s an integral . . The ratio between the quantum of work and the erg
is a rational number . . .
S: Represented by h.
A: Represented by h.
S: A definite number, they’ve worked it all out to a very fine decimal point.
A: Is the h you’re using here the same h as Planck’s constant?
S: Yes. It’s six point . . six point fifty times ten to the minus twenty-seventh.
It’s that small fraction.
A: Yes, I believe this is Planck’s constant.
S: And multiplying by that small fraction is the same as dividing by its huge
reciprocal. So when you multiply by that small fraction . . it’s stated in all the
books, you know . . you change it a little bit; sometimes it’s six point five six,
or six point five four, or something like that.
A: Uh huh.
S: But it is that six point five something, times ten to the minus twenty-seven.
A: Would you let me take a quick look at this? I would like to look it up right
quick just to see.
S: Sure.
/Interruption of tape/
S: Did you get the physics book? Can you see anything?
A: This is not a physics book, it’s a book on heat transfer. But it has . . .
S: It’ll be there, no doubt.
A: Yes.
S: Look at the index under quantum, it will probably tell it to you. You know where?
A: I know exactly where it is . . (Sound of turning pages) There are very elementary concepts here . . Lambert’s Law and Planck’s Law of Radiation. Six point six two four times ten to the minus twenty-seven. That’s Planck’s quantum concept. This is the one.
S: That’s right.
A: That’s right — “Erg-seconds.”
S: And the books repeatedly tell us that this quantum unit is an erg multiplied by that fraction. That’s a tiny fraction of an erg.
A: And so Planck’s quantum constant is equivalent to the minimum . . .
S: . . Piece of work.
A: . . work quanta.
S: The smallest piece of work that can come into our experience. Now they
don’t say that. They say “can exist.” But I can’t see any warrant for saying
that it can’t exist any smaller, but it just (laughing) doesn’t come into our
sensory experience, directly or indirectly.
A: I just wanted to be sure…
S: Yes, but it was six two, wasn’t it?
A: Six point six two four.
S: _________ It has been changed. It seems to me that’s higher than I’ve seen it.
A: This is in the CGS system.
S: Yes.
A: Now . . .
S: So now we have a tremendous variety of events, or quantities of work, that can make up our sensory experience, and thereby constitute so much of the objective world as is accessible to our senses. Not denying that there may be a lot more, to which our senses do not respond. (laughing)
A: Which is a good supposition, I would say.
S: Well you can hardly assume that just because our senses go so far, that
nothing else goes any farther! (Still laughing)
A: You do this at a very great risk to . . .
S: (Quickly) Yes, I would think so. That the whole cosmos should be
limited by our particular development (laughing) within it. So it looks to me as
though, if we consider that this cosmos of ours is a cosmos which is not
properly to be thought of as having structure, but as having mass units,
motion units and time units, which are capable of being integrated into
quantities of work which we call events, then we can have a philosophic
concept of the outer world, the whole cosmos, including ourselves for that
matter, as a world of events, and not a world of structure. Structure being
only temporary anyway; all structures come and go.
A: And also a continuum.
S: Continuum as events.
A: Yes.
S: Because events are always merging and diverging, and cross-connecting, transforming one another. They’re being shuffled all the time. You see what I mean?
A: You think that while events are made up of quanta, the events themselves are not quantized. There may be a continuum of events, even though events themselves are made up of quanta.
S: Well, a continuum in this sense, that there’s no necessary end to . .
The event ________ events, which are continually succeeding one another and continually merging and diverging from one another.
A: But an event is a discrete thing.
S: Yes — because of the discontinuity in nature, it is possible to
entertain ideas discretely and to experience events discretely. More or less discretely. But I think it requires the mind to perform the act of distinguishing. Our bodies probably don’t recognize . . . _________ I say probably . . . don’t recognize the discreteness of one event as distinguished from another except through the intervention of the mind. We have to perceive them, in their order of succession or otherwise, and then through the operation of the mind, we distinguish them from one another.
A: We use the mind for both functions — perception and conception.
S: Yes . . However, that’s not important to what I mean to get across. The idea is that when we examine the physical world, we are not really examining structures.
A: But it is important in this sense, that while the mind is perceiving, it may be unaware that there is not a continuum of events.
S: Oh, yes!
A: While the mind is busy perceiving, it may be under the impression that there is a continuum, while when it stops to conceive, it then recognizes that . . .
S: That there’s a discontinuity.
A: . . that there is a discontinuity.
S: Yes.
A: I don’t believe, come to think of it, I can’t think of how conception and perception can very well take place simultaneously in one mind .
S: It would seem rather difficult to think of.
A: In my own case I find it difficult.
S: Yes, I think so too.
A: At least, my perception, like the minimum perception required for driving an automobile, tends to be reduced when I am conceiving. For that reason, I don’t like to drive an automobile. I know of people who claim that they do like to drive an automobile because they can maintain this degree of perception while at the same time satisfying their conceptual exercises. But personally, I don’t find this satisfying. In fact, I think it’s dangerous in my case.
S: Some people love to drive automobiles; that’s largely an idiosyncrasy, perhaps, one person to another. It’s hardly relevant to the picture I’m trying to make.
A: No. Could I summarize two things now, to be sure that I have a proper understanding of your points? This logical structure stemming from the notion of three basic quantities, separate and distinct quantities . . .
S: Or units.
A: . . units, leads to a concept of maxima and minima from deduction. A maximum amount of motion, a minimum amount of motion, a minimum amount of time . . .
S: As soon as you admit your minimums, then your maximums are already there.
A: Yes.
S: (Laughing) That automatically introduces the maximum; you can’t introduce the minimum without introducing maximum.
A: Yes, and of course this brings to mind the analogy, or the idea, of a maximum velocity like the velocity of light and . . .
S: Not as a primary datum, but as a . . .
A: But as a result.
S: A derivative, formally. An analysis of the . . .
A: It’s a derivative. And the minimum amount of work, for example Planck’s quantum work, quantum energy. And then the other thing, important concept and one which is interesting to me because I think it contains a lot of food for thought, is the idea of quality in work, that you don’t get from considering it from the usual point of view. That there is a quality, in addition to quantity, which is . . .
S: Which is not dependent on quantity but is dependent on composition, a
word we use in all arts and constructs and so on. We are always composing
things — music composition and pictures, colors, poetry.
A: And while it’s not usually thought of this way in the physical sciences, the manifestations are there. As I was saying, availability is a concept in thermodynamics which is quality in work.
S: Related to human purposes.
A: Yes! Related to being able to do useful work. You have a certain
amount of energy, and the amount of that energy that is available for doing
useful work is called the availability. The availability is a property which
measures this.
S: It can be called quality, then, can’t it.
A: It could be called quality.
S: And therefore it’s inherent in the structure of the event itself.
A: It’s a property.
S: That’s right.
A: It only depends on the state of the system.
S: And it’s related to our lives. Because those things which contribute to
the advancement and reality — duration — of our lives are most esteemed
by us. Those things which tend to shorten our cycle are least esteemed.
A: Well this concept of social energy of yours is of that sort of energy.
S: It springs from this, right from it.
A: Did it spring from it, or did it suggest the physical interpretation? Which came first?
S. (Pause) I’m afraid I can’t be sure. But I like to think that the physical
foundation came first. I’m disposed to think that, but I can’t be sure. Whether I filled it in, you know, to support my . . I might have found that my social conceptions were hanging in the air and they needed some underpinning, and I resorted to this quantum analysis to find the underpinning for it — that could have been. On the other hand, I may have been intrigued by this quantum, and ___________ . . I think that must have been it — because I was tremendously intrigued by it, and then I found that it would sustain my social analysis. And my social conceptions came about the same time, just about 1932, largely on transatlantic steamers, reading Eddington and others, Planck, and so on, and taking their fundamental definitions and trying to see what it was implied by them. And I came to the conclusion, tentatively at least, that they had missed the point . . at least there were implications, inherent relationships in their fundamentals, that had become obscured because they had tried to impose Euclidean conceptions and non-Euclidean conceptions, on top of those things. And that had distracted them from seeing these relationships that I have been pointing out to you. Eddington lays it down dogmatically, that there can’t be any such thing in nature less than a quantum of action (laughing). A quantum unit.
A: And that’s a postulate of his?
S: Well, it’s an assertion, a dogmatic . . There’s nothing to support it! (Laughing)
A: Oh, well, there’s at least this to support it. If it works, then his postulate stands as a utilitarian concept . . or abstraction.
S: Well he insists that this thing is objective and that it appeals to our senses, this quantum unit does. But . . .
A: Well his assumption is a derivative of your analysis, and so . . .
S: Well he assumes that there does not exist in nature any less unit than the quantum unit. Well there’s something I wanted to call your attention to, not too prematurely, but dismissing his assumption as unwarranted and recognizing that it’s only what comes within this particular octave of our spectrum of objective experience . . .
A: Our band-width.
S: Yes (chuckling), that fits very good — band-width. . . . and that within that band-width, that’s all that can make up our physical world. But the reason it’s all is because our senses have only developed so far. We can go back in history, biological history of man ____________ our senses _________ our octave was much shorter.
A: Uh huh. It’s been growing, all the time.
S: Yes, and there’s no reason to assume that it’s stopped growing, that we won’t be able to perceive with the eyes higher frequencies than the ultra-violet . . . we’ll see the ultra-violet with the eye, or the sub-sonic with the ear (laughing) as we develop the ear, and so on. So that, dismissing his dogmatic assertion that there can’t exist in nature anything less than the quantum, we have the best of grounds for inferring that this objective world of oars is a very little bit of the whole world, and that there’s a subjective world.
A: Even if man can’t perceive with his senses these things, he can still expand his bandwidth and decrease his threshold . . .
S: Imaginatively.
A: . . . by creating better tools of analysis and measurement and so forth. In other words, with his mind, with ideas, he can increase this octave of his whether or not his senses evolve to greater ranges.
S: Yea, but I have some doubt . . I’m not dogmatic about this . . whether the use of sense extensions we have called apparatus, you know, and refinements of sense, whether they do extend the range. It looks to me as though . . .
A: I don’t think they extend the range. Let me see if this isn’t . . .
S: (Quietly) I have to cancel and withdraw that, that’s too broad a statement.
A: Let me put it this way. I don’t think it necessarily extends the
range, but what it does is, it makes a transformation from one octave to
another.
S: In the telephone, then, /it/ reduces high-frequency electrical
impulses to low-frequency sound impulses doesn’t it; it’s a
transformation.
A: It brings these events into our octave.
S: I don’t hear your voice over the telephone. Your voice has been transformed into electrical waves and these have been retransformed back into sound waves. Which are different sound waves altogether from the sound waves that came in at your end. (laughing)
A: Uhhuh, but by virtue of Bell’s ideas, we’ve come to accept this
transformation as being a valid one . . .
S: Yes.
A: So that we no longer think when we talk over the telephone that
the sound coming out of there is not actually the voice of the person
speaking. And that it is followed in time, also. It’s even displaced.
S: It doesn’t happen at the same time and it isn’t made up of the
same waves. It’s a different set of waves altogether.
A: Yes.
S: But they have the same mathematical characteristics as the waves at
the input. Input at the transmitter and the output at the receiver. They’re
different in time, different in composition; but they have the same
mathematical dimensions.
A: If Bell hadn’t succeeded in convincing his fellows that the
transformation was a valid one, he might not have been able to sell the
telephone. Of course that wasn’t hard to do, because they could recognize
the voices, probably. Not as well as we can now . . .
S: They /thought/ it was the same voice, too; they didn’t think it was
different waves. (Laughing)
A: But he had to know that they weren’t the some.
S: Oh yes, he had to know it. There’s a lot he didn’t know I’m afraid,
though, because he patented it as a toy, in the Toy Department of the
Patent Office.
A: He did ! ?
S: And apparently had no notion of its utility. But later, if not coincident with his patent application, he conceived it as an aid to deaf people.
A: But he never conceived of it as a commercial apparatus? A commercial innovation?
S: Well I think it became commercial, but rather to his surprise. That in the days of invention _____________ he didn’t anticipate that it would ever become a tremendous world-wide industry /laughing/ — a great international utility. National and international.
A: Edison was supposed to have been a very astute man who could recognize the commercial importance of his discoveries, and yet one of the most important ones was merely the laboratory curiosity that bears his name, the Edison Effect, which is the basis for the vacuum tubes and the thermal emissive devices that are used in electronics.
S: Uhhuh.
A: He never exploited those.
S: He never noticed the practical significance of those.
A: He didn’t conceive of the importance of that . . .
S: Having any practical value.
A: Yes.
S: The Patent Office has held for many years that the inventor doesn’t have to understand the theory of his invention. He can have a complete misunderstanding of it. But if it operates and the results follow what he describes, whether he understands it correctly or not doesn’t matter. (laughing)
A: Well I’m sure that’s the case applicable to this new type of power source I was telling you about a while ago. This man has not the foggiest notion . . oh he likes to think that there’s some cosmic energy conversion, and I wouldn’t dare . . .
S: (Laughing)
A: . . . argue with him right now . . until I were to calculate the energy density of cosmic rays or something like this, to be able to prove that this wasn’t the source. I would like to think at the moment it’s an electro-chemical . . .
S: Sounds like good sales talk for him. (laughing)
A: Yes. But he’s a layman. He’ s a man who is skilled in the art of mixing plastics, and making luminous paint, and things like this. He doesn’t even understand the chemistry of plastics. But he knows how to mix plastics very well.
S: Empirically.
A: Yes. He learned it and he does it . . .
S: Largely by imitation of others.
A: . . . and he discovered something by accident. But I’m not saying that this man is not entitled to . . .
S: Oh, no.
A: . . . to a particular idea or a particular . .
S: He’s serving civilization in developing these things.
A: Sure, sure, whether he understands it or not.
S: He’s entitled to his reward. Well I want to get this across to you so far, to suggest . . partly for the reason . . of suggesting that whatever occurs in this cosmos of ours is in the form of events — and generalizing _________ said before — and that events can have an enormous variety of magnitudes in enormous variety of compositions, almost infinite . . and perhaps infinite in magnitudes . . but that the part that we’re acquainted with /is/ only a tiny octave in the whole affair. I mean by the part that we’re acquainted with through our senses.
A: Yes.
S: We can discover more about the outer world, the astronomical world,
than our senses can tell us, by calculation. Our senses don’t tell us
that a comet’s going to come back in a certain year, or /on/ a certain day. (Laughing)
A: They don’t even tell us that the earth moves around the sun.
S: No. And so our minds can tell us a great deal that our senses can’t tell us. And then we can verify it through /our/ senses very often, as we can the sun and its motion. But it reduces to a very small objective universe without reducing the subjective universe, since our minds don’t seem to have these limitations, of recognizing only quantal events and multiquantal events. It leaves a whole world of sub-quantal events highly inferable in which, on a different scale, there could be a repetition of all that physics tells us about at the super-quantal level, multiple-quantal level. Physics deals only in quanta and multiple quanta, doesn’t it?
A: Yes.
S: And we have learned a whole lot about that.
A: Yes.
S: But this analysis that I’ve laid down to you leaves it almost a necessary inference that this is only a tiny fraction of the whole cosmos, the rest of which is not accessible by our senses at all. Our senses would have to be very much more refined, let us say, to increase the octave. Well then using an analogy, we know that beta rays, isn’t it, can be shot through the structure of atoms and rarely if ever encounter anything there. Is that right?
A: A beta ray? A beta particle? Well . . .
S: Whatever it is when we track electrons through the cloud chamber. Don’t we
track cosmic waves or . . .
A: Oh. Cosmic rays?
S: Or some of them . . don’t they call them betas, alphas or betas?
A: Well, alpha and . . . (sigh)
S: Well let’s say, here’s an atom. And we do shoot through that atom, as I
understand it, certain particles that do not collide with anything as they go
through except occasionally. Isn’t that right?
A: Yeah . . well, from my understanding of the nuclear physics, these rays, which are characteristic of the movement of certain kinds of particles, like for example electrons and protons and neutrons, and there are still other kinds that are not characterizable by particles. But a beta ray and an alpha ray are those radiations characteristic of electrons or protons, one or the other, I forget which. An alpha ray I think is a high velocity electron radiation, and a beta ray is a high velocity proton radiation.
S: Well that could be. We shoot them through cloud chambers . . .
A: Oh — the point I was going to make was that the cross-section for a collision
of atoms is different for these radiations. Each of these radiations has a
cross-section characteristic of its own type of radiation. In other words, take an
atom of lead. The collision cross-section that an alpha particle sees is different
than the collision cross-section that a beta ray sees. And a gamma ray, and a cosmic
ray, and an x-ray, and so forth. So that the density from the standpoint of the
collision of particles with the nucleus of atoms, is different in each case. It’s
not a geometrical quantity. In the sense of two automobiles, ______________ /they/
collide with each other with the same cross-section. No matter what their velocity,
in our realm of experience.
S: Well I’m only getting at the broad picture that particles do pass through
structures, and only rather rarely hit anything there.
A: Yes. What you’re saying is that even in material as dense as lead, there’s a
great deal of void there . . .
S: Yes.
A: . . . for these very high velocity particles.
S: So that the material is no denser than our brains, maybe. There are sufficient voids there for particles, so to speak, to go through without collision.
A: Yes. Uhhuh.
S: And then we can assume that /there are/ indefinite quantities of radiation
passing through any portion of our nervous system, or of our bodies for that matter, and we are only occasionally conscious of those — if they have a certain frequency and other characteristics.
A: They have to occur at a certain frequency, otherwise even the collisions
themselves, we’re not conscious of those either.
S: To impinge upon the retina, they have to have certain characteristics. But any
other characteristics, the retina /annuls?/.
A: That’s right; they have to lie within a certain frequency.
S: For instance the low frequency heat rays don’t affect the retina.
A: That’s right.
S: Well Tyndall proved that by putting a rabbit’s eye at the focus of heat rays from the sun — the dark part of the sun’s spectrum — and the rabbit didn’t bat his eye at all. Then he put his own eye there and took the heat rays right from the sun . . the same rays that would light the paper, the sane focus that would burn a hole in the paper, didn’t burn any hole in the rabbit’s eye and didn’t burn any hole in his eye. (laughing) Yet those heat rays were going through there.
A: Well the band width of the eye is fairly known quantitatively.
S: It’s short.
A: Sure, it’s very limited too.
S: Yes. Well I mention these incidents of that kind, rather to suggest that there can be almost an infinitude of events taking place which we are in contact physically, which pass through us, so to speak. And yet we have little or no consciousness of them. But that leads to this, that as our physical structure evolves, it may become more sensitive, as the eye is supposed to become more sensitive to higher, or lower frequencies, as it evolves.
A: Biologically speaking.
S: Yes.
A: Is there any evidence to support the supposition that man’s senses are evolving towards greater sensitivity?
S: There is biological evidence that the forms below man have a very restrictive sensory apparatus compared to man. For instance, they find a simple mollusk of some kind has the rudiments of an eye, which can only distinguish quantitatively, never qualitatively — as the different grades of white and black, or gray. And it’s doubtful whether dogs can distinguish . . .
A: See colors.
S: . . . in colors. Though they’re very keen at distinguishing sounds, I believe, and scents. So that as our sensory apparatus has evolved, and may yet evolve, we may become conscious of events that we now know not of. what did Hamlet say? “There are more things in heaven and earth than are dreamt of in your philosophy?”
A: I don’t recall the quotation.
S: “There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are dreamt of in your philosophy,” was it? At any rate, all of these events may be going on infinitely . . or indefinitely, to which we have never been exposed, that /is/ we didn’t have the receptivity for it.
A: Well we’ve been exposed to them, but we weren’t aware of them.
S: I mean that we didn’t have the receptivity to become aware of them. And it may be that man may have only very rudimentary senses and is substantially unaware of events. That just as a particle passing through a structure at the atomic level can be . . only occasionally strike fire — register there — maybe these people who have psychic senses only occasionally, and in a certain sense special conditions, are sensitive to these events to some degree.
A: Like what, for instance?
S: Well this phenomenon of ESP — extra-sensory perceptions — and things of that kind.
A: Oh, yes.
S: Those things may hinge upon a partial degree of sensitivity, so that occasionally one can get a glimpse of a different frequency of vibration than what comes to us ordinarily. It might account for how we can make guesses in these laboratory experiments — and make it better than the mathematical chance tell us about. There may be particular concatenations . . .
A: Could this account for any successful induction, possibly?
S: I would think so. We could infer that the whole psychic phenomena can be a matter of events taking place at sub-quantal levels.
A: Is it that rare combination of circumstances which allows a man to come up with a successful induction once in a lifetime, possibly, like for example . . well some men do it more than once. But if you come up with a successful generalized hypothesis that works and becomes a theory or a law . . .
S: It seems to come out of nowhere; you /don’t/ know where you got it
/but/ by intuition or something.
A: Yes, Yes.
S: Well that could be supposed that there had been sub-quantal events . . I always regarded a quantum as an event, either an action or an event, and multiple quantities of events. Then there may be corresponding sub-quantal events. I don’t know any reason why there shouldn’t be, except our own limitations which make us infer there might not be. (laughing) So it may be that whole sets of these things are . . impressions are coming into our sensorium, into our brain cells and so on, that bit by bit make a pattern. And when enough of these different impressions from different sources have come in and made a pattern, why we see it rationally. /laughing/ We see it consciously, rather.
A: Once the . . .
S: __________ a hypothesis which gives the ground for considerable inferences for psychic phenomena.
A: Yes . .
S: And yet it’s not incompatible, it’s almost necessary inferences from known physical phenomena. (laughing)
A: Well naturally, once an inductive act has been made and is successful, deductive results are not very remarkable.
S: No.
A: They occur with high frequency, with relative ease . . .
S: And yet sometimes we carry the inductive data around with us . . .
A: Yes.
S: . . . before it jells. (laughing)
A: And possibly . . well it’s interesting to consider that the successful induction of a principle in terms of this very rare collision, you might say, or having, let’s say, having a window open, in the sense that /you/ wake up one day and turn the radio on and pick up Australia, on that particular instant and on that day when you get Australia on your cheap AM radio, you have a certain rare set of conditions which has opened up a window and allowed you to extend your range of communications, which would otherwise be impossible considering the specifications of the radio and so forth. You might . . it’s very interesting to think of induction as being this sort of thing, because otherwise it’s a complete mystery. It isn’t classifiable. Induction is, to me, something quite different from deduction.. There are no formal rules, for example, to use for induction, as there are for deduction.
S: Well I went on for some months one time, not able to understand
mysterious circumstances affecting my business. And things seemed to work so strangely . . and unfavorably to me in a business way. I lay in bed one morning, and all at once I saw a whole lot of elements which would make it perfectly understandable. They had been accumulating in me unconsciously for a long time, now they’ve jelled. I went and told it to my business associates. “Oh for heaven’s sakes, why didn’t we see that long ago.” Perfectly plain, what was happening. (laughing) And so I think that there can be sub-quantal events which take a psychic form. And until they accumulate, as a certain train of waves has to accumulate before they can possess enough energy to cause a quantum jump . . .
A: There’s an analogy here too . . .
S: It accumulates and jells, and you get a flash. And ________ get a musical composition that way, or a line of poetry, or a plot for a story comes to you. You’ll have spells when you don’t get anything anymore, and then all of a sudden, there it is! (laughing) And the hypothesis I laid you down, the first one, on purely physical grounds accounting for the three extremes of physical events, raises a strong inference, almost an inescapable inference, that there must be such a sub-quantal world.
A: Yes. And that world, many people like to rope it off and say it is of the Divine,
which . . .
S: Which only increases the mystery!
A: Yes. I’m afraid so.
S: But the analogies I have made brings it out so that it is completely understandable, in terms of itself, it doesn’t call for some extraneous, miraculous explanation.
A: Yes, that’s why I like it. You see, to me there’ s lots of room to support
the notion of a Deity. The evidence . . .
S: Oh yes, there’s . . .
A: The evidence . . there’s so much evidence to support the notion of a
Deity, I find it difficult to believe that . . .
S: Yes, our mind can grasp the characteristics, too, because our minds
are not subject to limitations of time and space.
A: Yes. But the fewer things that rest upon suppositions of the
characteristics of the Deity, that is, the Creator, I’m talking about now . . not
the creation, but the Creator . . the more satisfying it is to me to call this
understanding. Because anything that depends on supposed characteristics of
the Creator, as opposed from the creation, this is outside the limits of knowledge.
A man is limited by his band width, of course, to perceive the creation. But he
isn’t limited, as you pointed out, in making transformations from outside of the
domain to inside of it. This is still knowable. The limits of knowledge are
increasing, are expanding all the time, both up and down. But there are things
which are unknowable. For example: . . .
S: (Cautioning) I wouldn’t postulate that, I’d have to know it’s unknowable. I’d have to have some grounds for an assumption like that.
A: All right, I’ll pose a simple question. The creation itself . . .
S: Is an assumption.
A: It’s an assumption. That’s right. We’re assuming that there was a time
before which there was no creation. When you talk about creation, you assume
there was a time before it.
S: Before which there was no time! (laughing)
A: Yes. There was a time when it all started. There was a zero. I don’t
find it very . . .
S: A zero. I’m allergic to zeros, and infinities.
A: I’m not very interested in this particular zero. I don’t . . .
S: Or any other zero, perhaps.
A: And therefore I say that this zero .. beyond the zero is unknowable. That’s all I’m saying.
S: Let me tell you, there’s a physicist of repute who has written a book in
which he . . .
A: Of good repute?
S: I think so, the book was given to me, or loaned to me, by a Dr. Wilson,
who’s head of an engineering department at Harvey Mudd College of Science and
Engineering. And I looked it through, and the man in his Preface said that the
book was only part of his work, that he didn’t have the funds to publish more
than a hundred and fifty pages of it, or something like that. And later he had the
other parts in mimeograph, and Dr. Wilson lent me the mimeographed parts.
Well it looked like an orthodox physicist in the main, he had formulas, or
equations, explaining different kinds of physical phenomena, which he said were
transformed from the regular by eliminating zeros and putting units in place of
zeros. It intrigued me very much. He had great difficulty getting up any attention
to it, it seems. And he never got enough funds to get the whole thing published.
And I took it back to Dr. Wilson, somewhat hurriedly because I had had it too
long, and neglected to get the name of the man; I want to write him a bit, for some
more of his ideas.
A: Was this recently?
S: It was about eight or nine months ago. Somewhere in Oregon, he lived.
A: Are you familiar with the book by Bridgman, The Nature of Physical Theory?
Do you have that book?
S: No, I only know his better known one, _______________ operation, operative tests and so on.
A: Would you like to have that book? I’ve been racking my brain, to think of a
book you might not have.
S: Yes, I’d like to see it.
A: The Nature of Physical Theory. It’s a short book. It’s kind of rare, I have it
myself, but it’s . . .
S: What’s the best known book of his, Bridgman’s? I knew Bridgman slightly.
Dead now.
A: (Incredibly) Is he dead now?
S: He died a theologian, and a good deal of a negativist, unhappy to say.
A: I’ve read just a few statements of his out of the domain of physics.
S: Does this what I’ve been talking about remind you of it?
A: Percy Bridgman, from Harvard.
S: A strong individualist, a free enterprise man.
A: Yes.
S: He started a movement, I don’t know how successful It was, in the realm of the physicists’ societies to combat the communist infiltration there.
A: I’m not familiar with that. I . . .
S: He took up arms against the communists in the physical societies.
A: I wasn’t aware of this.
S: This was several years back.
A: In fact, I thought he was still living . . .
S: I knew him in 1938. I got acquainted with him at the International Congress for the Unity of Science in Cambridge in 1938. They had foreign scientists and all there, and I got acquainted with quite a number of people, including Bridgman. I kept up the acquaintance with some of them later on. Most of them are logical positivists and so on — to my mind they were clear out of the realm of sensory experience, /in/ the imaginative realm. (Laughing) And while I have respect for chess players . . .
A: They’re like the fishermen and the net, most of them.
S: I have respect for the chess players and the creators of all kinds of
geometries . . it’s logical consistency and all, but it isn’t founded on premises
that are amenable to the senses. (Laughing)
A: Or if not, if it’s not that, it may be of a very specialized or limited field that they devote themselves to. The left hind leg of a flea, and that sort of thing.
S: That could be too.
A: But this book by Bridgman, I haven’t read it in about eight years. At the time
I read it . . .
S: What’s the title of it?
A: The Nature of Physical Theory.
S: Yes, that might be intriguing to me. There are a number of books that I meant
to look at. My grandson gets me books often because I express an interest in them.
I don’t seem to have the gumption to go and search them out.
A: Well don’t get this one, because this is one I would like to give you. I’d like
to get it for you.
S: Don’t give it to me, just let me look at it.
A: No, you gave me a book.
S: (Laughing)
A: I don’t mind owing you a book as long as I can think of something . . I don’t
mind receiving a book from you, but I like to be able to reciprocate, and now I think
I’ve found one that might be worth reciprocating with.
S: Well I’m happy to find that a man of your understanding of physical laws . . physics as it’s known today, is willing to look at something possibly more fundamental . . .
A: I’m completely satisfied with the development, I would like to listen
to it again on tape . . .
S: But remember this though, that we only assumed that there were fundamental units of the three kinds in nature. We haven’t proved it.
A: That’s right, so . . .
S: And I think it’s logically . . do you know curiously I knew a thing for some
time but it’s escaped me lately. There was a long time I couldn’t reason anything
more than an assumption that there would be units. I then developed a very fine
argument of the necessity for it. And then that’s faded out of my mind again. I’ve
tried to reach it several times, and my memory’s never any good for remembering
things back. But as you think more of it . . I found more of it, there’s more reason
for the necessity that there be such physical units, and I think it’s based upon this,
that there has to be discontinuity throughout nature, and if there isn’t any
discontinuity below certain magnitudes, let us say, if there’s no discontinuity
there, then there’s no rationality there.
A: You see what you run up against here with many scientists, is that they hold firmly to the view that there are no discontinuities in nature. I know a lot of my colleagues will support this assumption vigorously
S: ________ for engineers that would be true.
A: There are no discontinuities in nature. Well, in a limited way you could
say that’s true, there aren’t any . . .
S: Statisticians could say there weren’t any exceptional units __________.
A: Yes.
S: I was telling some of this stuff of mine to the Natural History Society at Johns Hopkins University, and when I put in a plea for using the same method of analysis at the social level as we do at the physical level, which of course is my specialty, Dr. Klinger, who was a professor of physics at Johns Hopkins at the time and president of this association, he wanted to ask the first question. He said, “Mr. Heath” — “Dr. Heath,” he said, as /people/ so often do, honoring me with a degree which I haven’t got — (laughing) . . he said, “In view of the unpredictability of human behavior, is it possible to have a science of society in the same sense that we have a science of physics?” I said, “No, Dr. Klinger, in view of the unpredictability of human behavior, it’s no more possible to have a science of society than it is to have a science of physics, in view of the unpredictability of that electron of yours.”
(Laughing, then both laughing). A molecule doesn’t know . . it has no sense of direction. This is exactly the same way that . . well this constitutes a logical contradiction in those people who ultimately subscribe to the collectivist notions of social organization, in looking at people in the same way that a physicist looks at an electron. There are people to be herded and coerced and caused to flow between potentials which are created by the state, in exactly the same way as electrons are moved around in a circuit by an electronic technician. They fail to take into account . . .
S: ______________ called rationalizing.
A: . . . that any science of society worthy of its name has to account for
the natural properties of human beings in the natural state, you might say,
and they have to include free will.
S: And their idiosyncrasies — of which free will is one idiosyncrasy. They don’t
have to be all alike in that respect, but statistically they’re very much alike.
A: Sure, and that’s through statistics that we can get quantitative . . .
S: Over-all quantitative.
A: . . . descriptions of societal action, and societal behavior. You can’t look
at one individual and say that on a basis of his drive, you design a society on the
basis of that particular model. On the other hand, I think that any theory of human
action that doesn’t take into account some basic, common property of all men, some
property that all men have in common, if it doesn’t take this into account, it is
not appropriate either.
S: Think of this: the atoms are highly different from one another, aren’t
they.
A: Yes.
S: They do make molecules, don’t they.
A: Yes.
S: By reason of a property that we used to call “valences.”
A: Yes.
S: Now if they have that in common, a property of associative capacities . . .
A: Affinities .
S: What else do they have to have in common?
A: Well they don’t have to have anything else in common to form a basis for a
science called chemistry.
S: Exactly — and if they don’t have things diverse, they can’t form any molecules.
They would only form aggregations. And as we know, properties possessed by the
molecules weren’t possessed by the aggregative atoms.
A: Yes, if there hadn’t been this postulate in the beginning, there wouldn’t be
any science of chemistry.
S: And so society exists because of the fact that human beings have one
property in common, . . .
A: I can only think of one.
S: . . . /the/ property of reciprocal associative relationships, and they don’t have to be alike in any other respect! (laughing) I don’t mean to say that they have no other common property, I mean there’s no other necessary.
A: Right. And this reciprocity is on a basis of mutual benefit.
S: Yes, it becomes spontaneous. It springs from the wills . . the combined
will of the two, because both wish to be reciprocal.
A: Yes.
S: And there’s a reconciliation of the will of man with his fellow man.
A: As far as I’m concerned also, this is the only thing that you need upon which
to base a social science.
S: And the more unlike you are in other respects, the better you can serve one
another.
A: Oh, certainly. We may even have a friendship, but all we need to know about
each other is that there is a common desire to have a reciprocal exchange for
mutual gain . .
S: Some common objective.
A: Yes, we don’t even have to know what the objectives are, just . . .
S: Yes, well if you have a contract and the contract is express, we express what
the objective is.
A: Then we know.
S: _________ a combined objective.
A: We may not know this at the outset, but because we know that each other has objectives, there may be some basis for exchange which we may explore. We wouldn’t do it otherwise.
S: Precisely. (Pause) This economic system of ours is based upon a profoundly beautiful philosophy, if I may call it. It’s susceptible of philosophic analysis that’s very revealing, and we find that it’s in complete accord with the best . . with what the world has accepted as the best in all the religions. And particularly, in the Christian religion. And as an indication of this being a fact, let us look around the world and see how people live. Let’s look first at the Christian world and see how long they live, how much they eat and what level of satisfactions they have — how much leisure they have, how much /they are/ free of economic necessities, by which none of them are compelled to act in certain ways — the liberation of the human spirit. And after you’ve drawn a line around them on the globe, let us say, you find all the people it included are nominally, at least, Christian people. The only people who are excluded are people who starve, have to breed like flies to keep the race alive and perish at around thirty years of age. But the Christian people are people who do the Word — without understanding it or realizing that they are Christians, or that /they are being/ hornswoggled by the theologians — pseudo theologians, I would call them because I believe in theology, as I do in religion. But I don’t believe in the false stuff — done for pelf or for prestige or for the exercise of power over their fellow men. Very little difference historically between the theologian and the politician. (Laugh) Same difference there is between the medicine man and the war chief of the tribe. (Referring to the tape recorder:) Is that thing going?
A: I think we have a few more minutes.
S: I’ve been spreading myself here unknowingly, exposing myself to attack perhaps!
(laughing heartily)
A: No, I promise you.
S: No? (Still laughing)
A: No, as a matter of fact if you’d like, you can take this tape and listen to it and see if you’d want me to keep it.
S: I wouldn’t bother about it.
A: I just wanted to record one of our conversations . .
S: If anyone takes enough interest in my stuff to challenge me, why I like it all
the better.
Mrs. Manning: If you’re finished, why don’t you record the date now.
A: Well this is recorded on the Sunday after your 86th birthday . . .
S: (Chuckling)
A: . . . which makes it January the seventh, I believe it is.
S: Four days after my birthday. This was my mother’s birthday, by the way.
A: Today, was your mother’s birthday?
S: Un huh . . seventh. And that reminds me again that she died on my birthday, and four days later, had she lived, she would have been eighty-four.
A: Longevity is a characteristic of your . . .
S: Yes, except in the case of my father, who died of what they said was acute stomach trouble, I think he was about 28 years old.
A: Oh.
S: Probably it was appendicitis, they didn’t know about it at the time. People can die of appendicitis very suddenly, you know.
A: Yes.
S: And I think they called it acute stomach trouble at the time.
Mrs. Manning: Before Mr. Heath was born. He never knew his father.
A: Really?
S: Yes, I was like . . Sir Isaac Newton and I, we’re very distinguished persons
_________________. (Laughing)
A: Well I should say this also, it’s 1962 — because I hope this tape is going to last a long, long time.
________________________
Metadata
Title | Conversation - 2037 |
Collection Name | Spencer Heath Archive |
Series | Conversation |
Box number | 14:2037-2180 |
Document number | 2037 |
Date / Year | 1962-01-07 |
Authors / Creators / Correspondents | |
Description | Transcription of a conversation between Heath and Alvin Lowi, Jr. at the latter’s home at 4018 Merrill Street, Torrance, California. Alvin’s wife, Guillermina, and Mrs. Frances Norton Manning, Heath’s hostess in Southern California who arranged and taped this meeting, were also present although mostly in another part of the house. |
Keywords | Lowi Philosophy Science Physics |