Spencer Heath's
Series
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 2038
Fragment of transcribed conversation between Heath, Alvin Lowi Jr. and others probably at the Lowi home at 2146 Toscanini Drive, San Pedro CA (this part of San Pedro later incorporated into Rancho Palos Verdes, CA), soon after the Lowis moved there from Torrance. Undated but subsequent to Item 2037 to which reference is made.
SPENCER HEATH: So many grams means so many grams per unit of motion.
ALVIN LOWI: That would be momentum . . .
S: Yes.
A: . . . in the mechanical sense.
S: MV. Not forgetting that V means that motion is so much motion per unit of time, just as mass is so many units of mass per unit of motion. So multiplying these first two together, mass through motion, which means of course through space or length, we have something we call work. But we also have another aspect of time called frequency — how often does this quantity of work get performed, and how often does this happen in one second? Then quantity of behavior is obtained by multiplying by the durational factor, which is how long does it carry on?
A: You know what I think we have here? I think we have at least an analogy in the physical sciences between continuum physics, which uses time as a continuum . . .
S: Umm Hmm (Agreement)
A: . . . and you might say, statistical mechanics, which uses time and all the quantities as discontinuous units.
S: And we’re pretty well assured now that all events are discontinuous. If they were not, we could not distinguish one event from another.
A: Do you want to move this? Are you finished with it?
S: Yes, thank you very much. I liked it.
A: It’s not very tasty without the sauce.
S: . . . But having a certain species of event — one following another of the same species, like light waves — we’ll get the quantity of action involved there by multiplying by how many units of time the thing carries on. That’s durational time. How many times it repeats itself is durational time. How frequently, or how many of these things happen within the unit of time, is called frequency . . .
A: This is more descriptive of the lifetime, or the durability, or the structure of this event.
S: Well the number of lives per year . . and now I’m speaking of men, though it sounds like insects, doesn’t it? (laughing)
A: No, it could apply to any . . .
S: . . . number of lives per year. The insects might have a thousand generations in a year. And that’s high frequency. No insect lasts very long . . .
A: No — or accomplishes very much.
S: .. and that’s short periods. And whatever duration it has, however, must be multiplied by the number of time units through which it continues to repeat itself. That we call durational time. In your electrical and other things you have the frequency of the wave, not of the current. It is fixed by a large number, indicating how many of those waves are embraced within a single unit of time. Then when we find that this process, happening within a single unit of time, carries on through many units of time, and multiply accordingly, that we call durational time. And without durational time, we don’t have any event at all. We may have the proportions in which events are composed . . .
A: We have rates, but we don’t have any integral.
S: We have what is properly called energy, and it becomes what is properly called action. And that’s why some of our writers have pointed out so much and insisted so much that actuality, the actuality of the quantum, is energy multiplied by time. Now it is. All action is energy rate multiplied by time. Because energy is not action.
A: This is a new concept to me, since I’m not familiar with the quantum physics, the concept of energy multiplied by time. This is called an event?
S: The only difference between the quantum event and any other event is the magnitude. In their versatility, they can be composed in different proportions. But all events can. And the quantum is just like any other event, except it seems to be the border line between what human beings can experience, directly or through instruments, and what they cannot experience. But our sensory system doesn’t respond to certain things . .
A: What’s the physical significance of the product of energy and time?
S: Well you get us out of the abstract into the concrete, into something that we can experience with our bodies. The energy is simply a rate — how many times this one thing happens or exists during one unit of the other thing.
A: Well, this is…
S: It’s the rate.
A: The rate of, say, doing work.
S: How much you do, in one hour.
A: That’s power.
S: That’s capacity to do work. It’s called power, it’s called act . .
no. It’s called energy. Well we’ve got it all mixed up. You can find it
called all kinds of ways. But however let’s go back a little further. We
have force and velocity, don’t we. FV, or MV, same thing. And we have FD,
which is force through a distance. I should have begun with that. That’s
a bit of work, isn’t it. There’s no doubt about that being a bit of work.
A: No, that’s right. But it’s not a rate, you could take . . .
S: And work does not necessarily involve any time . . .
A: It’s the same energy, whether this F traverses this D in a year, or whether it traverses it in a second. That’s the same amount of energy.
S: Right. Same amount of work done.
A: Yes.
S: So time is no object . . . (laughing)
A: According to the book.
S: One event is just as good as another. (laughing)
A: That’s what that says. That’s the classical idea of work.
S: But when time is an object, then we ascertain how many units of mass are associated with a certain number of units of motion, during one unit of time. So you don’t get into the actual world, objective world, until you multiply by time. Time is the actualizer. And that means time not in the sense of frequency, which is how little time anything occupies, but in the sense of durational time, which is the large time that something occupies.
A: The conclusion here is that the classical concept of energy, or work, is a pure abstraction, that energy . . .
S: Energy yes, but not work — because force times distance is work, regardless of time.
A: Exactly. Yes.
S: The way time comes into it, and it always has to be there . . .
A: But for this work not to take place within a certain span of time, is not sensible to a human being, physically.
S: No, it doesn’t entertain negatives. They’re unwelcome guests, never
admitted. (laughing)
A: Like for example, if I watch this clock over a space of time, I may hear it ticking but I don’t know it’s doing any work because I can’t see the hands move. So I don’t see any work being done here, and so I conclude no work is being done. But if I watch it long enough, in other words I increase my observational duration, I can see that the hand does move and that work is being done.
S: The velocity is slow because there are many time units in relation to one motion unit. (Long pause) Let’s go back again. Force through distance is work . . (correcting himself) . . force through motion is work . . .
A: Motion being a displacement.
S: . . . because the centimeter measures motion the same as it does distance. In fact you don’t know anything about time or distance except in terms of motion. (chuckle) So force times distance is a certain amount of work. But you can’t exclude the time factor there, it’s part of what constitutes the event. As soon as you introduce the time factor, you find out force moves through a certain distance how frequently. And that’s called the rate of work.
A: And the rate of work in engineering is called power.
S: It’s called energy. (quickly) Yes also power. You’re right. Potential — and the rate is the potential. Now you bring time into it and find out how many of those events happen — through how many periods of time that particular event or series of events happens — and that’s durational time. That gives us body. Now force times motion alone has no . . as I said, has no time in it. Your body cannot experience it. So it’s an abstract conception called a ratio. So many units of force through so many units of motion. That’s a ratio, it’s not a happening. It can’t happen until the time comes in.
A: This is the old classical concept of energy . . or I mean of work.
S: There’s no difference in any concept, they’re all reconciled.
(pause) But if a certain amount of work occurs, during one unit of
time and your work extends over more than one unit of time, you
must multiply that certain quantity of work by the number of units of time through which it extends. That changes it from the abstract to the concrete, from the subjective to the objective. When that durational time comes in saying how long, that gives it substance. How long it operates. How long from the beginning to the end of this event. The event has a certain work rate, and that work rate multiplied by the number of units of time involved, gives you the totality of the work. That’s what you get . . you change work from being a mere abstraction. Force times distance is an abstraction, you can’t experience that. That is, without something else to be there. You have got to have periodicity there, or time. You’ve got to have so many time units or time periods there. So when you have, as an abstraction, force through a certain distance, is so much per unit of time, well how many times does that happen? How much have you got? — Well find out how many units of time you have. And multiply what you started with by the number of units of time, and that gives you a definite, concrete quantity of action, or power if you want to call it, or event. So the quantum principle doesn’t involve anything new — which we discovered. A kilowatt hour or an erg second, we talked about this before, I think, is a definite quantity of work occupying one second of time — one times one times one.
Rosie (?): Daddy, we have more company.
A: Excuse me a second.
/Tape discontinued, begins
again when guests arrive./
_____________________________
S: . . . respond to you in a certain way. And then after I heard him,
then I couldn’t respond. (laughter)
A: Are you insinuating that I’m a distraction?!
S: I would like to be so considered myself; if I couldn’t distract anybody I couldn’t have so much influence. (laughter) Anyhow you _________without distracting, anyway. /Force/ and reaction are equal and opposite. If I attract you, why then . . .
A: It’s bound to be a distraction.
S: You are distracting me. (laughter) Am I right, literally right? Correct?
I think it is . . I haven’t thought of it in those terms before.
A: Certainly!
S: Newton was right, profoundly right. Not only in the physical world, but
in the biological world, the psychological, all the way around, everywhere.
A: You realize this has implications in the social sciences? The First Law
of Motion? . . .
S: Goodness, yes!
A: For every action there’s an equal and . . .
S: I’ll say.
A: . . . opposite reaction? For every attraction there’s an equal and
opposite distraction? (laughter)
Guest: Subtraction too, maybe.
A: This can be reciprocal or destructive . . .
S: You can’t subtract from one thing without adding to another, can you?
A: But you can . . .
S: Can you add to one without subtracting from the other?
A: But this combination of attraction and detraction can produce more than
what you started out with. For example, if I distract you in such a way that
you come to a conclusion out of things that you had been thinking of, without
actually contributing to this conclusion, you have more than you started out
with. You have now a conclusion that you might not have had. So that this
distraction and attraction can be reciprocal in the sense that you use it.
S: There are two aspects of an event. One aspect of it is compositional and highly variable. The quantity of force and related to the quantity of velocity. EVe = Energy, a rate of action, doesn’t it. If FV represents work, or action, but F..E = M or v2 . . .
A: Energy equals Mv2
S: Yes. That’s not the square of energy in the literal sense, because you can’t reduce it back into a quantity, a rate into a quantum. _______ is a rate, a rate of energy or a rate of action — you can’t reduce it into a quantity until you multiply it by time. And then it’s called a quantity, and that’s why you have to make it Mv2. E = Mv2. And Mv2 over 2 only means that you’re using double velocity, when you take the terminal velocity under acceleration.
A: Kinetic energy is the terminal velocity . . .
S: Yes.
A: . . . that is reached by a particle which started out with a
certain potential energy.
S: So if you assume uniform motion, E = mv2, without any 2. Now v2 is not v2, if __________ — every working physicist will tell you it is. It just happens that in the unit that we take, there are the same number of units of velocity that there are of time. In your experiment by which you assume the acceleration of a gram at a uniform rate of acceleration, through one centimeter during one second, now in that the gram and the dyne go together, numerically, always. You might as well use one as the other. And velocity and time go together, because they increase or decrease in perfect unison. A unit of velocity increases the same as a unit of time.
A: You mean a unit of displacement? Centimeters?
S: Yes. Because when you have a falling body or any accelerating body, the velocity increases with every unit of time. There is an increased unit of velocity.
A: In uniform motion.
S: Yes, now when you multiply velocity by time, you get back to length, or distance, don’t you. So v2 is velocity times time, not velocity times velocity. Otherwise you wouldn’t have your old force times distance. You’d have two kinds of action, or power. So the little economy device, to use the exponential method: Instead of saying vt, we say v2. That’s how it works out, practically. Not many people have thought enough about it to realize that. It’s hard to conceive. But it’s absolutely demonstrable.
A: That there is an equivalence between v2 and vt.
S: Yes. And if there were not, you’d have work or action consisting in a force through a number of units of motion — distance or length — and we know that’s action, that’s work completed. It’s all there, isn’t it. Except that we haven’t stated how much time. Time is there also. Now when we bring time into it, then we say not so many units of motion, but so many units of motion associated with one unit of time. Now then when we say how many units of time there were, and multiply by how many units of time there are, and that gives all the units of force and motion that there were. It reduces velocity to length. You can say that work consists in force times length, can’t you?
A: Yes . .
S: When you say force times velocity, times time, then you have said force times length. Force times motion times length.
A: Well there is an equivalence here, because conceptually, force
times (velocity)2 is energy, and so is force times velocity times time.
S: Exactly. And since time and velocity always go hand in hand, neck
neck, it doesn’t matter whether you call it v2 or vt. Numerically, they’ll be exactly the same. And that product gives you what we call a quantum, or a quantity, which a large quantum. If many quanta, it’s
quantity; and if it’s only one, a very small quantity, it’s quantum. So this more complicated formula isn’t any more complicated . . it
appears complex only for the reason that you have used one symbol
for two different things. And you can do it legitimately, practically, because the same numbers of those things always appear in the event. It’s similar with the mass and motion. We take mass in so many units, and we don’t mean so many units absolutely, we mean so many units every time you have a unit of length, or a unit of velocity. Ten pounds means ten units of mass for every time you have a unit of motion — every time you have a foot — so you multiply them together. And that’s a ratio between a mass, or force, and a unit of motion, or distance. We’re not conscious that that’s a ratio, because it’s already multiplied when we say “ten.” (laughing)
Guest: Yes I see, your force divided by the acceleration, actually, or which is again velocity, or time it involved . .
S: And when we come into velocity, velocity only means how much motion there is for each unit of time . . or how many units of motion there are for each unit of time. So velocity is a product of motion and time — how many units of motion you have per each unit of time. Now to get it into action, or work, you have to multiply it by how many times this thing happens, and that’s durational time, that’s not frequency; velocity is frequency, how frequently does this happen during one motion of time.
A: . . What’s the frequency with which a unit of length is repeated.
Repeated.
Guest: Continuously repeated.
S: And then when you want to get your whole unit of length or your
whole unit of work, which include the _________, why then you multiply by the number of units of time that are involved.
A: . . How long has it been going on.
S: Through how many time units.
Guest: In other words you integrated over the time range.
A: Yes, that’s what we sense.
S: And your bill isn’t written up until we take into that account the energy rate multiplied by the number of time units through which that rate was continued. Durational, or continuation time. And these
mathematically happen to be reciprocals _________. If the fraction, as I was saying a while ago, is 4 over 4, there’s no ratio at all. Ratios can only exist between two different numbers. If the numbers are the same you can’t say what the ratio is, unless you say one to one . . .
A: You don’t consider unity a ratio.
S: No, because unity is only one, and it takes more than one to make a ratio. One is not a number, in other words. One is the basis of number, but one is never properly considered a number. Because a number means a number, it doesn’t mean one! (laughing)
Guest: ____________ more than one.
S: It means more than one. How are you going to have a number when you
have only one? (pause)
A: Yes, the generalized number has to represent quantities of digits.^
Guest: That’s right, and one is just a unit.
A: One is just a counting unit. (General agreement) Well what is a zero?
S: Well that doesn’t come into our experience at all, so we might as well forget it. (General laughter) Subjectively yes, we can use it.
Guest: Yes.
A: It’s an important abstraction.
S: You know that star towards which the mariner points his prow is only subjective, he never can experience it. (chuckle) It gives him direction and helps him to navigate, the same as zero helps us to think. And infinity is the other star, the other end. We never experience it in any possible way or means, but it gives us direction.
A: You experience it in the sense that it stimulates your retina.
S: Can you see infinitely far?
A: No, that star might not really be there, that’s true, but . .
S: The fact that you never get to infinity doesn’t mean that you’re
not making any headway.
A: Infinity might come to you, though.
S: I think it would have to come a pretty long distance, probably, but I don’t know anything about that. I don’t pretend to tell you anything about infinity. I’m not so constituted that I can entertain conceptions that large. (chuckling) Nor am I so constituted that I can entertain quanta — events that small. I’m in a sort of an octave, and as our physiology develops, then we can expand that octave — or else we might be still amoebas.
Guest: Well in the scale of things, man is just about in the middle isn’t he? Of the scale of observable things, like ten to the minus C over twelve for the electron, and on the other hand it’s ten to the twelve centimeter for the observable scale of the universe?
S: Yes, I read some books to that effect. Man is a kind of a “middle man.”
A: Middle of the road again! We’re always in the middle. (General laughter)
S: There are interesting books about that, man’s dimensions . . .
|
A: Well I’ve wondered about that myself . . .
S: He’s intermediate.
Guest: Yes.
A: That the smallest scale of measurables is about as far on the opposite side of the zero as the largest scale of measurements, mathematically speaking — same numbers of powers of ten.
S: Yes, just as much minus as there is plus. And yet there isn’t any minus unless there’s something for it to be less of. Because a minus sign is a sign of operation.
A: Well this isn’t minus, this is one the other sign of . . .
S: Nothing.
A: One. It’s on the other side of one.
Guest: Actually a division, even.
A: One is the division. Ten to the zero power, or one, is not zero. It’s
not negative. It’s below the size or magnitude of one by the same number of
powers of ten as the largest number is larger than one. It’s digits to the
right and left of the decimal point, the distance to the farthest star that
we can see, or galaxy, is the same number of centimeters to the left of the
decimal point as the size of an electron, the diameter of an electron let
us say, is in centimeters to the right of the decimal point.
Guest: In one way you’re just adding the centimeters, you know, side by side, whereas in the other one you’ve taken a centimeter and started chopping it down as small as you can. (laughing)
S: Yes.
A: Yes that’s a good analogy.
S: And we’re about as far one way as the other. That may be an accident, but more likely there’s some reason for it . . if we only knew the reason.
Guest: There may be a teleological reason for this.
A: A what kind?
S: Teleological? Yes, there could be.
A: A what kind?
S: Max Planck lays it down that it’s only reasonable to suppose that the
units involved in the non-reversible are just too small for us to understand
so far. When we understand what units are involved, then we’ll know what
numbers are there, and then we’ll have the rationale. But we don’t know these
universal events in nature, just because we can’t measure them. That can be
because the unit employed in those events is below the magnitude to which we
respond.
A: Our experience . . .
S: There again is a place for a metaphysical world.
A: Once again our experience prevents us from concluding that this isn’t also rational. In other words to presume that just because we can’t . . .
Guest: Understand
A: We haven’t yet experienced it or understood it, doesn’t mean that it
isn’t rational . . .
S: Precisely.
A: . . . and epistemologically within understanding.
S: And that’s the huge mistake, the vast mistake, in Werner Heisenberg’s
little book, The Philosophy of Science, with an introduction by philosopher
F.C.S. Northrop, a long introduction, urging that below a certain — or
uncertain — magnitude, uncertainty prevails. One of the most drastically
irrational things that you ever could conceive, and it’s accepted by everybody
so far as I know . . there may be books against it. But I’ve annotated the
margins and on additional leaves stuck in right on through. It’s the most
irrational thing I ever encountered.
A: It’s typified by the statement you hear often, “Don’t look for reason where there is none.”
S: Yes. Well having assumed that there is none, don’t look there. (chuckle)
Guest: Is this Heisenberg you’re talking about, the one who came up with
this complementary idea, or the principle of uncertainty?
A: The Uncertainty Principle.
Guest: Yes.
S: Sometimes called the probability . . statistical probability.
A: He’s talking about some kind of rationale, anyway.
S: Think in terms of events. When any event happens, or has happened, was
it certain or uncertain? After it’s happened, is it certain or is it
uncertain? Before it’s happened you can say it’s certain or it’s uncertain,
but that’s how you feel about it; it can’t be any less certain before it
happened than it was after it happened. Except for your limitations — you
impute that to it.
A: So you can’t predict it, but that doesn’t mean it’s not certain to
happen.
S: That’s what they call vitalism . . now what’s the word for it that Aristotle called it? Animism. You think this event has some kind of a reasoning capacity something like yours, and no more. Well I can’t think of anything more repugnant to my mind, than that a thing becomes certain by happening and was uncertain before it happened — if it’s the same thing. You say at once, accidents happen. And we can often trace the cause. And if we can trace it — it comes within our understanding — then we say it was certain to happen. Now if it transcended our understanding, and we didn’t know whether it was going to happen or not . . .
A: Can’t find the cause.
S: . . . then we say it happened by accident. Chance. Now when things happen
many times prevailingly, statistically in a certain manner, we then assume here
must be some cause there, and that’s statistical certainty.
A: And then that’s an excuse for not understanding . . .
S: Exactly.
A: The root cause.
S: And so we call it statistical certainty, meaning that it hasn’t become certain to us yet. But in those statistics it was certain; those statistics knew what they were coming to, or whether they were going to come out. (laughing) If they didn’t, then they’d come out in great variation.
A: I think it’s quite unfortunate that such a powerful tool as statistics in the hands of some people becomes an excuse for poor reasoning.
S: ___________ the saying is, there are three kinds of lies? Plain lies, damn lies, statistics. (laughter) Plain lies, damn lies and statistics. Or numbers . . .
Guest: Sophisticated lies. Numbers don’t lie, but liars can. Let’s see . .
A: Figures don’t lie, but liars can figure. (laughter) There’s an awful of
that, but you don’t blame it on statistics, I don’t think. Nor do you use
statistics as an excuse to stop looking for causes, which is what a lot of
physicists do. It’s still a tool . . .
Guest: ________________ a mathematical tool which is properly used, I can see where you would probably derive some advantages from it, but . . .
S: Yes. Oh, greatly.
A: It’s a damned good substitute for explicit cause and effect. But it’s
only a substitute, the way I look at it.
S: We haven’t ascertained the cause. And when we haven’t ascertained the
cause, yet we know that prevailingly things have to happen a certain way, we
assume a cause.
Guest: We sort of try to make it fit the facts.
S: And that’s what we call statistics. We assume an unknown cause, like the
unknown god, you know, by its effects. We assume the unknown god by his effects
— as the Greeks did, you know. So we assume the unknown rationality by the
effects — that it comes out statistically in the same way always. Statistics
came into a little experience I had one time. Dr. Klinger, Professor of physics
at Johns Hopkins University, invited me to talk to his group, a physical society,
about social organization — we being the atoms or the quantum units and so on, or
whatever your unit is, and interacting with one another.
A: The individual as a unit.
S: And so I spread my stuff that the physicists ought to study society, the individual same thing as though he were an atom, and finally perhaps as though he were a molecule, and get the statistical results — the whole society as though it were a mountain perhaps, or some big structure. And so I gave my ideas, which were looked at of course with somewhat skeptical eyes, and when I finished my plea, that they should proceed in social science in the same manner that we are proceeding in physical science, by assuming a unit and getting the numbers and all that sort of thing, as I had put out in some detail under what I called “The Energy Concept of Population,” which makes it possible to use all the simple arithmetic that we use in counting any other objects . . .
A: /Aside to Guest/ It’s very elegant, you should read his book on this.
S: Then Dr. Klinger wanted to ask the first question. And he said, “Dr. Heath,” . . . some of those people are so used to doctors they call me a doctor; I missed it by a year or so . . Doctor of Civil Laws it would have been in another year. And so I don’t claim any title to that effect, but I tried to quote it literally. He said, “Dr. Heath, in view of the unpredictability of human action, or behavior, is it possible to have a science of society (which is the title of this book of mine), in the same sense that we have a science of physics?” And I said, “No, Dr. Klinger, I am sorry to say, but in view of the unpredictability of human behavior, it is no more possible to have a science of society in the sense of physical science, than it is possible to have a science of physics, in view of the unpredictability of your electron.” . . The “No” was an ironical “No.” (chuckles)
A: It was no more possible to have a science of society in view of the unpredictability of the individual, as it is . . .
S: It’s just as possible.
A: It’s just as possible because of the unpredictability of the fundamental units of both.
S: I put it in the negative, “No, Dr. Klinger . . .”
A: You put in in the negative.
S: “No, Dr. Klinger . . .”
A: But yours was sarcasm!
S: . . . in view of the unpredictability of human behavior, it is no more possible to have a science of society than it is to have a science of physics, in view of the unpredictability of your unit.” (laughing)
Guest: In that sense, sometimes I wonder whether, like a while ago we brought out the fact that it is Schroedinger who claimed that life is a tendency toward decreasing entropy, but on the other hand when you look at it in this respect, individuals’ unpredictableness and so forth, it would seem like you could look at it the other way, as tending toward an increasing entropy.
S: Yes . . .
A: Except for one thing . . .
S: . . . when events mingle and commingle and cross-current and converge and
diverge and form new events, when that’s happening, the elements of mass,
motion and time are being modified — reproportioned is what I mean to say. And
so some of the ensuing events from the next instant, or next motion, the next
period of time, will have a greater element of time in them at the cost of the
other two features.
Guest: (Agreement)
S: And so the ensuing events, those which most prevail will be those which contain the most time. So time is a qualifier of reality . . it gives us the quality of reality. That’s why you multiply your electric rate, your power rate, by time to get some reality when you pay your balance.
A: This is not the continuum time but the interval time.
S: Yes. Time with relation to whatever unit you’re talking about: Planck’s quantum unit, an erg second, a kilowatt hour, or whatever it is, the amount of time embraced in that unit gives it the amount of reality that there is there. Now that doesn’t qualify it. The quality of it /is/ to satisfy human desires. And that’s what all quality is. It depends on the ratio between the force and the motion; that is, the higher level of frequency . . .
A: You don’t think time enters in as a characterizing feature of the quality.
S: Except in the sense of frequency it does. In the sense of how often, but not how many times. Duration there means how many times. But how often — frequency — is the qualitative characteristic, because /an/ event changes its nature, its quality, without its quantity being changed at all. And any change of an event of a given magnitude, like a quantum or an erg second, any change of (pause) . . of a given size, as I said, a fixed size of event . . .
A: Magnitude.
S: Then time determines nothing but its magnitude, right?
A: The presence of it, the quantity of it.
S: How long it takes it to happen. But the other two elements, the force
— the gram element — and the centimeter element, they can be highly
variable. And that’s frequency.
A: You’ll find that . . .
S: How many centimeters per unit of time . . (pause) . . of time, yes.
Guest: ___________ time units.
A: These always could be talking about the reciprocal relationships
between men, these are reciprocal events rather than destructive ones.
Unless you qualify it, you usually mean that, don’t you?
S: No, because what we call destructive events are those which are running into higher frequencies. The collision results in things coming up into radiant energy, you know. And it’s the conflict of collision between the elements in the radium that causes it to send its energy out into high frequency rays. And so with men, it shortens our lives. When we collide with one another we live shorter lives, and it takes the same quantity. And it takes the same quantity of human lives, a larger number of short lives, to make up the same as a small number of long lives.
A: (To Guest) It’s one of the conclusions of his book that the reciprocal
relations, the ones that are non-destructive, result in an increasing
duration, or lifespan. And this is in harmony with the decrease in entropy
that goes along with creation, whereas the destructive . . .
S: Destroying is higher frequency.
A: . . . events are tending toward the counteraction of the decrease in entropy due to creation.
S: Let me give you another little anecdote which actually happened. (pause)
I was riding on the train between Detroit and Lansing, and a professor of
physics sitting on the seat with me wanted to talk. I like to talk with
professors of physics, I like it very much; but I was much absorbed in an
article in a magazine I had, and I wanted to finish it. So I fended him off two
or three times while I finished my reading, and then I turned to him and
engaged in conversation, and learned that he was a physics professor . . no,
of chemistry . . in the University Michigan. It was Michigan College then. And
we talked along casually and nodding, making similar observations to agree with
one another, until he made some mention of this doctrine of entropy. By that
time he knew that I had read some in that field of course. And I said, “Well,
that’s where I can’t go with you. I agree with you up to this point, but that’s
too much for me.” “Why,” he said, “do I understand you correctly?” “Well I mean
what I say.” He said, “You confound me. You seem like a man of reading and
scholarship. I wonder at this; I can’t understand it.” And I said, “Well I’m
having the same kind of trouble with you. I don’t seem to be able to understand
you. But there was a time in my life when people used to tell me that water
always runs downhill, and I believed them.” He said, “Well doesn’t it?” “No,”
I said, “I don’t believe them.” That’s where he said, “I can’t understand you.”
I said, “You do believe that water always runs downhill?” He said, “Why
certainly.” “Then please tell me how it gets up there.” (Laughter) “Now,” I
said, “they used to believe that energy always ran downhill. The time came . .
Professor Schroedinger, he’s found that it goes uphill part of the time. (Some
laughter) If you would read Schrödinger’s little volume on that called What Is
Life, I think you might get some light on the subject of what is life.
A: I’ll have to read Schroedinger. He wrote a masterpiece in 30, 40 or 50 pages, not much more than that, on statistical thermodynamics, which is a real masterpiece.
Guest: Who did?
A: Erwin Schroedinger.
Guest: Oh.
A: I haven’t read this philosophical . . .
S: I said, “I can explain this to you, I think, because just as in my young life water always ran downhill, it was only for one simple reason, they didn’t see it going up.” (Chuckles) “If they’d seen it going up, they wouldn’t have said that. But it happens to be transparent as it goes goes up, and so they thought what they didn’t see didn’t exist. And maybe you feel that way about this — you don’t see it!” (Laughter)
A: Of course the analogous thing to this in economics is Bastiat’s book,
That Which One Sees and That Which One Does Not See, in coming to the major
conclusions of the classical economists.
S: Well what statement can we make, of any certainty, about what we cannot
see? I had a disturber in a discussion group one time who was always saying,
“Now I can’t see…so-and-so and so-and-so.” And he got to be a little . . he
wasn’t very vociferous or _________ and so he didn’t cause much trouble, but
you always knew what he was going to say. Mr. Mosher was his name. And so on
one occasion I said, “Now Mr. Mosher, I think everybody in this room
understands that there are a good many things that you don’t see. You’ve been
telling us for some time about them. Now won’t you just as a favor to me, on
this occasion, tell us something about the things that you do see?”
(laughter) “Because,” I said, “I’m sure that it can’t be but what there are
some things you do see.” (laughter)
A: The positive approach. (laughter)
S: ____________________ speculations there.
A: It’s the things you don’t see which always turn out to be the most important things.
S: No . . .
A: It’s the things you don’t perceive directly but have to conceive of, that
turn out to be important.
S: Yes, because that makes you a creator, you have to use your power of imagination, your conceptual powers, and often you use them mathematically, and by that mathematical process you see things with the eye of the mind that your eye of your body can see also — for the first time.
A: Because it knows where to look.
S: Yes . . well that showed them where to look for Neptune. Neptune was
discovered by the eye of the mind. It showed . . Faraday’s next man . . it showed . . Faraday’s data was taken over by one mathematician . . .
A: Einstein?
S: No, no. He was a contemporary, a Scotsman . .! Always know the name . .
A: Of Faraday?
S: Yes, he discovered the electromagnetic spectrum by mathematics.
Guest: Maxwell? Maxwell the one?
A: Maxwell, yes.
S: Maxwell, exactly. Maxwell took the quantitative data — it had to be
numerical to be used mathematically — and he manipulated it mathematically,
according to the uniform laws of mathematics __________ laws of the mind, as
you know — also the laws of the atoms and the levers and the gears and
everything like that — and he discovered the whole field of the electromagnetic
spectrum. And some thirty years later Hertz in Germany discovered it, not with
the physical eye but with the physical senses. So we didn’t discover Neptune by
this eye, we didn’t discover electromagnetism . . .
A: Well the discovery of Neptune . . was it Neptune or Pluto that was
discovered by applying Einstein’s mechanics to some observational data on
. . Uranus? No, Uranus is a farther star . .
S: Uranus was the way it did it . . through Uranus’ perturbations that
they discovered Neptune, and it was through Mercury’s perturbations that . . what else was discovered?
Guest: Pluto was the latest planet, some people don’t know whether it’s
really a planet . . .
A: Yes, okay. It’s the discovery of Pluto that was the ultimate
confirmation of relativity.
Guest: That applied there?
A: Relativity was used to deduce the existence of another planet of a
certain mass that would be in a certain place to produce those kinds of
perturbations in the orbit . . .
S: I don’t want to be a spoil-sport in this field, but I want to remind
folks that once in a while under the Ptolemaic system we predicted eclipses
and a whole lot of things and carried on navigation, all on a wrong theory.
Guest: You mean this epicycle thing through which . . .
A: Yes.
S: All on a wrong theory.
A: (Laughing) All on a wrong theory! Well what’s wrong with ________
S: Einstein had predicted things, and they’ve been verified. In the same
manner that Ptolemy predicted things. But that’s no more guarantee that
Einstein has the right theory any more than that Ptolemy had the right
theory. We should remember that. I believe in Planck as the fundamental
foundation. I must say this to you: . . .
/Conversation interrupted
by arrival of more guests/
______________________________
Guest: (As new arrivals come in) Big night!
A: Oh no!
New guests: Look who’s here!
Guest: Well I haven’t seen you for a long time!
A: How have you been? You’re looking good! Mr. Spencer Heath, this is Mr.
Lou Safer.
S: Mr. Lou Safer?
L: How are you.
S: Not Lucifer? (laughter)
L: Well, that’s what they call me sometimes.
S: (Laughing) It sounds pretty bad.
A: Sit down, Lou.
S: Well let me show you something I think is very fitting, on the foundation of what I’ve been saying. That every event is made up of so many units of mass, so many units of motion and of so many units of time, in some proportion. The quality of the event — whether it saves our lives, shortens or lengthens our lives — is dependent on the frequency, which is the relation between the mass, or force, and the velocity — the first two elements — and the motion. The magnitude of the whole work or works — the whole works, if you like (chuckling) — is established by ascertaining the number of time units through which the whole thing extends. So you multiply the grams by the centimeters by the seconds, to get the magnitude of the action. Is that right?
A: (Agreement)
S: Now if that’s a very small product, we can’t experience it, directly at
any rate. But if there are any fundamental units of mass, motion and time —
like gram, centimeter and second — if there are, and I think I can pretty well
show by deduction that there are . . I have done so I think . .
A: Yes, we did that.
S: If there are, then there is a magnitude of mass less than which will not
enter into motion. And if the product of the three must remain constant – as
it always does in any event . . .
A: It sets a limiting value.
S: . . . whether it be a quantum event or not (h has the same magnitude the
same as erg has the same magnitude), the product of those three has to be
always the same. Correct?
A: (Agreement)
S: That’s the Planckian unit, the building block of the universe and so now
this is the picture. Now, let’s draw a certain conclusion from that picture by
assuming that in this particular integration there is only one unit of mass —
the fundamental unit of mass, the ultimate unit of mass.
A: Below which you can’t have a combination . . .
S: Below which there wouldn’t be any combination. And I’ll say for his
benefit that we have to assume that, or we assume there is a world without numbers. Because we would be in a world with no field of phenomena that would be rational . .that there would be an irrational field; some portion of our cosmos would be chaos. Because if we didn’t have an ultimate number we couldn’t have an ultimate event. We couldn’t have any rationality below that. There has to be a bottom unit in order to have a point above which you can have numbers. And a point ___________ you cannot have numbers, can’t have any rationality. So it leads to the conclusion that this is only part cosmos and part chaos, if it’s not fundamentally the same, and that contradicts our reason. Now getting back to this picture, we’re going to assume an event that has a certain . . a class or kind of events, like Planck’s quantum, or like an erg second, like a horsepower hour, like a kilowatt hour. Those events are all the same magnitude, are they not?
A: Given a kilowatt hour, then . .
S: Then all kilowatt hours are the same.
A: The same. (Agreement)
S: Given a Planckian unit, then all other Planckian units are the same, in
quantity at least. Not that the kilowatt hours are all the same in
composition; they highly vary. You’re transforming your currents all the time.
And it’s a constant aspect of the Planckian unit that h is always the same
magnitude, it’s the same particular fraction of an erg second, and no other.
Isn’t that right?
A: (Agreement)
S: Very good now, if we have a particular instance of a quantum, in which
the mass unit is at the bottom, it’s the absolute…
A: It’s the absolute minimum.
S: The absolute minimum. We don’t need to say that in absolute terms
exactly; anyhow, it’s below which it will not unite with any other elements of
an event, and therefore you can’t have an event — because you can’t have any
ratio. No number. So then let us go back and assume once more that the
particular event that we have . . the particular class of events, all having
the same over-all magnitude, but this one happens to have only one unit, the
ultimate unit, of mass in it. Well then in order that the product may be the
same, there must be a very large number of units of motion, which means a high
velocity. Is that obvious?
A: (Agreement)
S: And then how can there be any larger number of units of motion without
diminishing your mass? — your over-all ____________.
•
A: Presuming the mass to be your constant, letting the quantity of . . .
S: Presume your erg-seconds all being the same.
A: Presume a quantity of energy, letting the quantity of mass approach a
minimum, then the quantity . . .
S: The velocity has to . . .
A: The velocity has to approach a maximum.
S: Well now that’s why you have a maximum velocity of light, derived and
not assumed, as Einstein does. Einstein takes it as his basic datum.
A: A postulate.
S: Postulate; a priori. Now you see he’s taken a derivative conception
for a fundamental one. And when he bases his theories, so far as he does,
on that, he’s basing it on a non-fact.
A: So you have a more elementary postulate to make.
S: Yes, which physics . . .
A: That the world is rational.
S: . . .which physics is always demanding, too, to get at the rationale of
the cosmos. Because if it doesn’t have a rationale, it isn’t a cosmos; we’ll have to call it a chaos. And how do we recognize that? How do we know? How do you distinguish cosmos from chaos? Well we have a very nice answer for that, because /unless/ we haven’t been organized out of the same elements that all of the rest of the cosmos is, one of those elements is rationality. We’re a chip off the old block, we’re the same kind of wood. And there’s nothing in that block /but/ what’s in this chip. If it were not so, I wouldn’t know rationality when I see it! (laughing) Some say this is a chaotic universe, that man is sort of a chip adrift, a bit of rationality . . .
A: Random matter.
S: He has rationality in a hostile world — cynics say that — because everything else except man is irrational. You’ve heard that often, haven’t you?
A: I’ve heard it put the other way, everything’s rational but man, who’s irrational.
S: That’s what they say, in effect, that man has a monopoly on rationality, only they don’t know where he got it, if he ever did. His whole self, he got it from the cosmos. And if there’s any rationality in him, it’s in the place where he came from. (laughing) He couldn’t come from a place that he couldn’t bring it from . . (laughing) . . which is the whole cosmos. We’re segregated units as it were, abstracted from the whole cosmic whole. And if we have any such quality as rationality, there wasn’t any other place for us to get it from. And that’s why, when we see it outside of ourselves, we recognize it by the fact that it’s in ourselves. Or the religionists might say, the theologians might say, that’s at-one-ment with God.
We have the same faculty, the same kinship and so on. And which includes the faculty of creation, by the way, which we haven’t ________________.
A: That’s when they use the concept of God as synonymous with the
creation itself.
S: Yes. Man is only godly when he creates, and gods are always creators, in every language except the sub-man, who isn’t quite man yet. Because all his gods are devils, demons, he’s afraid of them. He doesn’t understand them, he’s afraid of them, and he’s afraid they will do to him what his brother is trying to do to him: prey upon him.
A: Whether he is or not.
S: And he can’t help that because all sub-humans, none of them create anything. And if they don’t create anything, whatever they consume, they have to consume each other — when they don’t produce their own food. And when they consume each other or consume each other’s food, which amounts to the same thing . . it’s obvious in marine life; they all prey upon each other. And we prey upon the vegetable life. Even when we eat animals we’re preying upon them; we’re eating the product of vegetable life.
A: (Agreement)
Guest: This kind of in a way reminds me of some of the philosophical concepts of the Yogas, the Yoga philosophy, so called, which states that the so-called material world of the body, as distinguished from mind or spirit, is nothing but the condensation of the ultimate . . the spiritual world, in other words the . . .
S: Yes . .
Guest: It’s a thought of the . . if you want to call this thing God, or the Absolute Being, or the Ultimate Self or whatever it is, the so-called material things are nothing but manifestations of the thought of this Ultimate Thing which is a sort of a condensed ________ , so to speak.
S: Let’s speak of the same thing from a slightly less nebulous direction. Let’s say that that part of man which is rational is the part of man which identifies him with nature. Man is an event, and an event is something that’s organized by rationality of the three elements which constitute an event — mass, motion and time. And the most real man is the man who contains the longest time — a generation if you have to take it statistically — and so just as Plato and St. Paul insisted that reality is that which most endures, so the physical reality is the reality which contains the largest element of time. Now then, it’s this rational faculty which seems to be independent of the bodily faculty. At least it’s not subject to the same limitations, because we can reason about things that . . .
/TAPE RAN OUT/
______________________________
S: . . . which can be conceived as infinite, can be conceived as divine, everlasting infinitely in time. That’s the third element in the Christian Trinity, which is Eternity. You read the Articles of Faith, the first article describes the Ultimate Reality as Father, Son and Holy Ghost — symbolically of course — then follows it with the parallel, Substance, Power and Eternity, being the same three aspects of reality taken in their infinite magnitudes. Now that excludes them from objective experience, because that all has to be in limited magnitudes. Finite magnitudes. So the physicist manipulates the same three elements of his trinity to satisfy men’s dreams and desires — to get to make what he wants, to change his environment the way he wants it changed. The way God did when he turned _______ chaos into order. So that the physicist has a way of mimicking God on the finite scale because he’s finite. But his mind doesn’t have any limits, and when his mind fully functions _____________ his mind he can create all the time, infinitely. But with his body he has to do finite creating. And so the theologian, something like the story of Cinderella . . the theologians and the philosophers _________ in the upper levels of the House of Life, where they can preen themselves with their infinite conceptions, while the scientist — Cinderella — getting his hands pretty dirty down in the cellar . . Cinderella or, yes, Cinder-cellar, wasn’t it? . . he does the real work. Because he deals in magnitudes that can be experienced, whereas the theologian deals in magnitudes that transcend any objective experience, believes that a subjective technique has done a lot of people good — and a lot of good. But it doesn’t take place in anything that the body can respond to. So the field of operation for the theologian is the field of subjectivity, the field of the mind, or spirit of man. The field of operation for the physical scientist is the humbler field down near the foundation of things . . where Cinderella operated and did a lot of things for her proud sisters of Philosophy and Theology and . . I forget who they all were; I’ve got them in this book of mine, I think. (Chuckle) And they preened themselves up there while Cinderella, working down in the cellar, does the real work, keeps the house alive. Not only that . . .
A: They treated Cinderella rather badly though, didn’t they?
S: Oh they did indeed. But she had her coming, and I was just going to say, science has its vindication coming. The fairy godmother is going to come along, and she’s pretty well on the way, towards lifting science into recognition as a being fit for meeting the prince. Getting back to theology . . . (laughing)
A: In spite of the theologian.
Guest: Yes.
S: Yes, and approaching their infinite aspirations, dreams, plans and specifications, in actuality. Now she does that because she has a foundation.
A: Is there an implication that the physicist can do, without that being his objective, what the theologian makes as his prime objective but can’t do?
S: Exactly, because he deals on a finite basis.
A: Yes.
S: The theologian deals on the infinite basis, which takes it out of the realm of human objective experience. If we could experience infinitely, if we had infinite capacities for experience, well then we could do business with the theologian.
A: That’s a nice example.
S: But all the business he does, it results in no profit. Because it can’t be used. Anything you can’t use, you can’t make any profit out of. (laughing) The customer has to use it.
A: No one can enjoy it.
S: Can’t use it to any purpose. But notice this. Some people rather disdain humble things, quantitative things; they know quality from the start. And (pause) the animal nature of man, which is his foundation — which he’s born with, and all his other properties have to be acquired don’t they? Everything that the infant does is something that all animals can do. But he soon proceeds to being able to do things that transcend the possibilities of animal life. Mainly, that he can conceive as well as perceive. The animal, being able only to perceive, doesn’t get very far; his reactions are instantaneous and not governed by his will. He can think of nothing in the way of creation, can practice no creation, because he doesn’t pause to consider, or pause to reflect, let us say. That was Thorndike’s notion wasn’t it, that intelligence consists in delayed reaction. That’s what makes man intelligent. So our foundation — our vital foundation — is an animal foundation. But we transcend the limits of that because we are also endowed with the power to dream — the conceptual power. Now then man, having this conceptual power, develops by certain rules that are laid down in certain religious precepts and so on, the power to transform the world in which he lives. You can’t sell power, or action; you can transform it — and get paid for the process of transforming it — into a different frequency or some different kind that you can buy and sell or otherwise make use of. So the foundation of our house of life is the animal. And some people scorn it: “Who wants to be an animal?” In fact I’ve heard religious people say, “Man is not an animal! The idea, it’s an outrage to . .”
A: Primarily an animal.
S: Animal plus. But they forget about the plus. As old Dr. Malthus did when he thought he had to starve to death. (chuckling) Man doesn’t have to starve to death, because he’s a creator. (chuckling) And so those persons who scorn the foundation of the house of life and want to get up into the realms of art and philosophy and all that sort of thing, without the animal foundation, they make me think very much of a man who would prefer to live in the foundation than to live in the upper stories. The foundation is a very important thing to have but it’s not the place where you want to live. (chuckling) You want it underlying — like that old Old Testament quote, “Underneath are the everlasting arms.” The animal life of man is that which supports him, he rests upon, and it wants to be good and sound and not built on sand, and that sort of thing.
A: Yes, the very fine philosopher wouldn’t be very fine for long if he didn’t have the minimum subsistence level.
Guest: Yes, or a person would have to have good health which is as you said, it’s down at the animal level so to speak. It’s your body.
S: You can’t make much concrete without sand. Also things called “aggregates” by engineers, aren’t they?
Guest: Yes, sand and aggregate . . .
S: So it’s interesting to reflect that the animal nature of man is his foundation, but it’s not his superstructure. It’s a very good thing to rest on, but not a very good thing to live in. (laughing)
A: The foundation again.
S: And I equate the reborn man, the regenerate man, with the man who has passed beyond the animal stage. The unregenerate man is the man who still lives in his animal nature. It makes sense to me . .
A: Which is most people, at the present time . . most people are still in the animal life.
S: Our species is characterized by the fact that it has some humanness about it. All species are so characterized. They must have a certain amount of similarity, fairly well specified — and that is a species, distinguishable from other species. But beyond that similarity, he can integrate himself, form higher organization like a society or even a family, because they’re radically different in almost if not every other respect except in respect of their capacity for integration with one another . . their valency, uniting with one another.
A: They have to be dissimilar.
S: The members of a family have to be dissimilar. Male and female have to be dissimilar, and so on. If all the peas in the pod were exactly alike, they would make poor neighbors. And there wouldn’t be any male and female there either I guess, if they do have it. (laughing)
Lou Safer: What would you call an animal, I mean the difference between an animal and a non-animal man — that some are and some aren’t?
A: Well, a man is an animal, but he’s more than an animal. That’s all. All men are animals, but not all animals are men.
S: Well the Old Testament tells us in the very first chapter, that he was made of the same kind of mud and so forth as the other animals, but that he wasn’t finished until he was breathed something like conceptual powers. He had to be able to hold images, he had to have imagination. And when he had that imagination, he was given the recipe for creating the thing which he imagined.
A: Not all men . . .
Lou Safer: Well you say some are and some aren’t.
A: . . .they all have the potential capacity, but not all of them exercise their capacity for conceptual activity.
S: Nor have developed it.
A: Nor have developed it. They can all perceive, but so can dogs and cats, you know. They all have to eat, or they have to have a minimum metabolic sustenance to live, like any other animal. But they live on each other. And man lives on them! (laughing)
A: If they can’t conceive of ideas to produce and create, then they wind up eating each other’s sustenance.
S: And they’re always disappearing, they’re always going extinct. Paleontology tells the story for millions of years back. They’re all on the road to death. It’s a death march. Now man isn’t on that road to death for the simple reason that he can create the means of living, the sustenance that’s required.
Guest: Sometimes I wonder about that.
S: But you see you have to make a distinction even here. Of all of the species known as humans, only a few of them have the powers of conception that produce the creation that does not require man to consume his neighbor’s sustenance. In other words, they know how to get what they want without getting it off each other.
A: Yes. But only a very few ever make this possible. But just because there are such a few individuals who have these conceptual powers and can create, that makes available to everybody else sufficient opportunity to live without consuming his neighbor.
S: Yes, they must have these conceptual powers — which are rational powers, quantitative basically — in order that they can produce anything, create anything. All the rest of creation is rational, and not until they learn the technique of reciprocal relations can they discover the technique of science. They must have differentiation of labor and different kinds of materials and all that. And they can’t get those things until they serve one another. So there’s a social technology, known as business, or exchange, or the golden rule, as against the primitive technology of parasitism and cannibalism which is carried on under what is known as the iron rule of sovereign powers: killing each other, extinguishing each other. So because man practices the creative golden rule, he then has a physical technology. So it’s this spiritual relationship of contract that gives him the power to command the waves, to command the sun and the moon . . . (chuckling). . to command the atoms and the molecules and all that sort of thing, as he’s doing. Penetrate space, and everything of that kind. They . . .
A: They had a contract with discipline . . .
S: Yes.
A: . . . in the case of the physicist working in the laboratory.
S: He has to deal with Mother Nature, if you like, or father God, as you choose, in precisely the way that he has to deal with his neighbor — which is divinely, which is creatively. To be a creator of the world around him, he must first cooperate with his neighbor. A single man could never develop sciences or engineering or any rational technologies. But group men, interfuctioning by reason of their dissimilarities, having enough similarity to constitute them as of the same species . . we’re all alike in that respect, but we’re unlike in every other respect so far as we can practice any rationality — because ratios can’t exist between the same numbers or between any identities.
A: Sort of like the example you gave a while back of the two men trying to get over that brick wall . . .
S: Yes. But neither one could get over himself.
A: . . . and pulling on their own bootstraps, they couldn’t get very far.
S: He pulls on his own bootstraps and he’s in nice equilibrium, but it’s a static equilibrium. You pull on each other’s bootstraps, there’s still an equilibrium but they go over the wall. That’s a dynamic equilibrium. And so while everything in nature balances quantitatively, they do not balance qualitatively. while man wants to live forever, wants to be like God — and we presume God didn’t do that way unless He wanted to — (chuckling) — so, to achieve his highest aspirations, he has to rule his environing world — use it as a basic material, and through first making spiritual engagements with his fellow man which are reciprocal and in which each does the will of the other . . in which each is doing the will of God, which commands it. And through that social technology then he commands the wind and the waves in what we call scientific technology. And now by this scientific technology, he recreates his environing world. By recreating his environing world and making it more habitable . . he’s the only animal that makes his habitat more habitable, by transforming deserts into gardens and so on, and doing that, he makes the conditions requisite for his physical life more favorable. If he acts in the other rule, of having things go down to entropy, then he makes less favorable conditions. He always lives, but under the one rule he lives more abundantly, and under the other rule he lives less abundantly. Under the rule of living more abundantly, all he has to do is to pursue that with some pertinacity and he’s headed for immortality — which is the ultimate towards which he can always approach asymptotically although he can never arrive — any more than the mariner arrives at the star which gives him direction and enables him to put his anchor in the right port. (chuckle)
A: He can live to immortality . .
S: He can approach it . .
A: He can approach immortality . .
S: Constantly approach . .
A: Constantly . . .
S: And fortunately we can never arrive. Because if we arrived to the end of time, we’d be in hell. (laughing)
A: But you mean by that . . (laugh)
S: We’d cease to exist.
Guest: The part becomes the whole, huh?
S: Yes..
Guest: Or tends to approach the whole in that…
S: Yes, or an h-o-l-e maybe.
Guest: (laughing)
S: A hell of a hole. (laughter)
A: You mean that by . . in succeeding generations, they would . .
S: Yes, to be sure. So the social relationship — which is the religious relationship of the Old Testament and the New — what is it? Love thy neighbor as thyself, and love him just as much as you would love yourself: Do just as much for him as you would /for/ yourself. And in the New Testament a little bit better: Do more for him. (Pause) Do unto all men as you would have all men do unto you. Which is a little more than you would do for yourself. And when you follow that command and obey that command . . or when you disobey it you’re sinning, and the wages of sin is death. But what is it. . the reward of obedience is eternal life. Something like that. These are myths, of course. Patterns of thought. They are good diagrams to go by.
A: These concepts may be put in much more precise terms though.
S: Than I’ve been using.
A: Yes.
S: My tongue is sort of thick tonight. I think I usually do better than . . .
A: I mean, you’re using the classical theological approach to explaining these things.
S: Allegory, and symbolism.
A: Yes.
S: Then let me ask you how you can have allegories running through hundreds of generations of men in different parts of the earth and races, having great basic similarity, unless they’re something that’s intrinsic in human nature.
A: Well you can’t.
S: And so the wish, the dream, the Cinderella dream and so on, or all the dreams . . .
A: I think the last time . . .
S: . . . are potentially possible because if we didn’t have it in us to dream it, to achieve it, we wouldn’t have the power to think about it, to conceive it.
A: The last time we got together, we were talking about the similarity in the two great discoveries of the Eastern and Western civilizations, the golden rule.
S: Yes.
A: Discovered independently, expressed a little bit differently, and I expressed my preference for what I call the negative, or Oriental expression of the same rule. The Christian golden rule is, “Do unto others as you would have them do unto you.”
S: It’s DO unto them. And the other is not do.
A: The other one is, “Don’t do to anybody that which you wouldn’t have him do to you.
Guest: Yes, you’ve put it on the negative side.
A: But they are logically equivalent if you are careful about your terms.
S: Well you know why sovereignty is supreme in the East, and is not supreme — because we have something more powerful, free enterprise – here, is for this reason, that /when/ men in free enterprise, under this golden rule, make an engagement or an agreement of a kind, they always agree to do something that the that other fellow wants — that he considers good. So every contract is an agreement to do good. And, by the way, you can only do that by finding out what your neighbor will consent to, and appreciate. With Mother Nature /it/ is the same; you’ve got to find out how she acts and on what terms she will do business. __________ those are natural laws, and then she will work with you. You don’t have to exterminate her or ruin her, at all.
A: Which you can do.
S: As fast as you understand your neighbor, his thoughts and his processes, then he will exchange with you _________ being reciprocal. And so as soon as you understand the modes of behavior of the general world — the natural world — you know that Mother Nature then is just as ready to do business with you. But you have to act on her terms, the same as you have to work on terms prescribed by your neighbor in business.
A: He’s part of the nature you’re dealing with.
S: Yes. That’s why it happens to be so ____________ you take the natural man, that portion of nature which is man, or all the rest of it. When this part wants to deal with the whole, he approaches it the same as he would approach another part. If he approaches another man, he says, how would you like to have your eggs cooked, and so on, (laughing) or how will you have your clothes cut, and all that sort of thing. And he’s very assiduous to do it that way. And on the other side it’s reciprocal; it works both ways. So when he comes up to Mother Nature, he has to say, “Mother Nature, how are you carrying on here anyhow? I’d like to get in on this.” And he finds out how Mother Nature carries on, and then she’ll do as much for him as he’ll do for her – according to her rules, the same as your neighbor will only work with you according to his rules . . so far as you follow his rules. So the thing is reciprocal all the way through. Wonderful thing about Mother Nature, though, is, she has so many more resources than we have that we seem to have the best of the bargain. But that isn’t necessarily so, because there’s such a lot of us. And as we get more and more, which we can get as we improve the environment . . at least instead of less and less, then we will have more and more dealings and get richer in life. But as soon as we cease to cooperate with Nature, she withdraws from us. And so when we want to get some services, I prefer to go to the multi-millionaire establishment because the millionaire can do a whole lot of things for me I can’t do for myself — or you can’t do for me either, unless you’re like him. So we’re always seeking each other out. That’s why these large corporations grow, you know. Because they get so many more customers, they can do so many more things, because they can do so many and better things for them. Now some would say, why do you pick him out? Well I’ve said that I go to the big store because they have greater facilities for serving me. I don’t go to the blacksmith shop for an automobile. (chuckle) And when somebody says as a moralist — moralists are always making some formal and wonderful objections — I said in a seminar today (someone asked), well what about the moral aspect of it? I said, “Well if there’s one thing I fear on the earth, it’s a moralist.”
Lou Safer: If there’s one thing, what?
A: Moralist.
Guest: Moralist.
S: If I’ve got anything to fear…
A: Oh . . (laughing) If there’s one thing I fear . . .
S: . . . it’s a moralist. And they caught me on it. They saw what I meant. But I want to finish this illustration. The only reason the millionaire can afford to do business with the likes of me, just one simple reason. (Pause) ‘Cause there’re so many more of us. That balances the books.
A: More of you than there is of him.
S: As Lincoln said of the common man, God must have loved the common man because he made so many more of them. (laughing) That was a pretty clever statement, I thought.
A: I was going to say that you can almost distinguish between tyranny and liberty on this basis. Or let’s say, the concepts of collectivism and individualism, on this basis. The collectivist looks at man as apart from nature, something that is putty in his hands.
S: And he’s been given authority over him.
A: Yes, and he’s been given authority over him . . .
S: Cain and Abel relationship.
A: Yes. The individualist, on the other hand, looks at each man as a part of nature which he must accommodate in his scheme of things. Each man is a sovereignty in the same sense that nature is itself.
S: When Cain asked God, am I my neighbor’s keeper, the answer should be “Yes.” He ________ keep him alive!
A: I’d better see about my visitors here, they may have to be leaving.
S: I guess so — and I should have been. I had a very short . . I don’t know what time I went to bed . .
(END OF TAPE)
Metadata
Title | Conversation - 2038 |
Collection Name | Spencer Heath Archive |
Series | Conversation |
Box number | 14:2037-2180 |
Document number | 2038 |
Date / Year | |
Authors / Creators / Correspondents | |
Description | Fragment of transcribed conversation between Heath, Alvin Lowi Jr. and others probably at the Lowi home at 2146 Toscanini Drive, San Pedro CA (this part of San Pedro later incorporated into Rancho Palos Verdes, CA), soon after the Lowis moved there from Torrance. Undated but subsequent to Item 2037 to which reference is made. |
Keywords | Lowi Physics Science |