Spencer Heath's
Series
Spencer Heath Archive..
Item 3077
Galambos correspondence – to, from or about Andrew Joseph Galambos
1961-2014
===================================================================================
===================================================================================
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 2823
Carbon of letter to Joseph A. Galambos
October 19, 1961
Dear Mr. Galambos:
I daresay that in some of your classes or other meetings, you are applying the principles of parliamentary procedure. I am therefore sending you 50 copies of my “Parliamentary Table” for ready reference during a meeting — thinking you may find it useful, especially on the occasions when communists or other dissenters try to take over. You may find these also good curricular material. You will doubtless note, from the arrangement of the Table, that it is adaptable for immediate use during the course of a meeting without any necessity for reference to the manuals from which it is taken. If they prove to be of any great use to you, I can supply larger quantities.
I am also sending you with my compliments a copy of the book, How I Discovered the Secret of Success in the Bible, written by my friend Clinton Davidson, who had a great deal to do with the financial founding of Harding College at Searcy, Arkansas, and who is at present similarly associated with Pepperdine and other Colleges. I am much impressed by the high degree to which our Judeo-Christian ideology lends authoritative support to the modern philosophy of free enterprise. You will of course understand that it is in the symbolic significance of our mythology, and not literally, that we find its idealistic practicality.
Mrs. Manning has written me that your school is off to a very fine start in Orange County. I was happy to see a copy of your publicity in the Santa Ana Register.
Looking forward to seeing both of you and Mrs. Galambos before many days,
Cordially,
____________________________________________________________________________
Penned note
November 19, 1961
Dear Spencer and Spencer:
You are right. I heard Galambos last evening and we talked until near morning.
As I appraise him so far, it is around 100%. And I do not often have a feeling even close to that.
Cordially,
Baldy
(Might tell Pierre Goodrich your impression of Galambos, as will I.)
____________________________________________________________________________
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 3077
Letter to Heath at Apt 11-C, 11 Waverly Place, New York 3, New York, from Joseph A. Galambos, Director, Free Enterprise Institute, PO Box 22189, Los Angeles 22, California, on Thanksgiving Day
November 23, 1961
Dear Mr. Heath:
I have been very delinquent in writing to you. I must assure you that it is not that I have not been thinking of you; quite the contrary, I have thought of you practically every day. I have, however, been completely snowed with work and I have not as yet come to the point where I can have a full-time secretary which I sorely need and which is the reason for my backwardness at corresponding.
However, today on Thanksgiving Day, I think it most appropriate that I do write you to say that I am thankful for the existence of such positive creative intellects as yourself and freedom-minded people such as yourself and Mr. Hoiles and Mr. Knott. I am very grateful to you for the introduction to Mr. Hoiles. I have seen him on a number of occasions since and I have subscribed to his paper since September (not to mention the growing number of subscribers he is getting through my classes). He is one of those rare human beings that fully understands a voluntary society and knows how to articulate it and on top of it, he owns newspapers. It is a pity his circulation is not in the millions. This is a remediable defect, however. Cur Free Enterprise Institute and CCI Bookshelf are just the ones that can remedy it over the long pull.
I am now happy to report to you that our enrollment in four locations is 140 compared with 42 in two locations the first time the course was offered. We are now halfway through the course. The next offering will be in February. We will be giving it in Orange County and continue our LA locations (four of them). We shall be going to San Diego or San Francisco before too much longer… We are expecting von Mises and Leonard Read next year for short one-week long courses each. I spoke with Mr. Read while he was here in October, and I spoke with Dr. von Mises last summer.
I am happy to say that we are beginning to interest some people in your book and we have sold about half of those oh hand. It takes a while, but we’ll get it rolling. Your Progress and Poverty Reviewed pamphlets are selling quite well and we are nearly out and will have to reorder.
I hope you will be back by December 15th. If you are, we wish to invite you to a private dinner where our company’s management will host four elder statesmen of freedom that we respect: you, Mr. Knott, Mr. Hoiles, and Mr. C.H. Hoiles. On our part those present will be my wife, Alvin Lowi, Donald Allen (manager of The CCI Bookshelf), and Billy Robbins, the patent attorney I mentioned to you who is now our corporation attorney. These, on our part, are the management of our overall enterprise, as of now, in the earliest stage of development. Those invited (you, Knott, and the 2 Hoileses) are those we know locally who are respected by us and of an older generation. We wish to discuss with you the mechanism whereby we plan to build a society of voluntarism and freedom and thereby effect a complete defeat for all forms of collectivism and win a complete victory ideologically for CCI upon which an enduring society can be constructed. The title of this very private and confidential presentation is “The Total Strategy of Victory”. Were Dr. von Mises, Mr. Read, and Mr. Hazlitt present in California, they too would be invited and ultimately we hope we can do this. Meanwhile, we hope you will be here. If not we shall proceed with Mr. Knott and the two Mr. Hoileses. We will then discuss it with you when you do return. However, we do hope you will be back.
I am sorry I have not had the time to fulfill my intention to finish your book as yet. I have given a lecture almost every weekday night since you left. Four a week for my course and nearly every Friday a presentation someplace. I have been working on other related matters including the items includable in the total strategy. I have been to San Diego and to Sacramento and to San Francisco for presentations and/or lectures. We hope the course will be offered in San Diego by February but this is not sure. I am also gratified with the nucleus of interest we have in San Francisco. Among the people present for my San Francisco presentation was Dr. Harper who seemed to be most favorably impressed. We discussed you also. He has sent me some books to read pursuant to our meeting including a prospectus of the Institute of Humane Studies. I have been bombarded by literature to analyze, pass comment upon, and other advice from various sources – some fundamental such as Harper and Read and The Freeman and others less so. It is small wonder, that with my extremely slow reading speed I am still not finished with your book. When I do, I plan also to read Spencer MacCallum’s thesis. Meanwhile, I have to do it in small snatches which is, of course, not the ideal way to do it.
This week, on the 2nd, I am giving the Symposium on Freedom for Samples. Also, on the 16th of December (two in a row).
I hope to see you soon, sir. Meanwhile I certainly wish you the very best of health and continued well-being. I look forward to seeing you, hopefully on the 15th. If you are back then we shall meet at Knott’s Berry Farm for dinner and then have the discussion
Meanwhile, the best of everything and please forgive me for not writing sooner. I was thinking of you most kindly daily. My wife joins me in our best wishes as does Alvin Lowi and Don Allen.
Respectfully,
/s/ Joseph
Joseph A. Galambos
P.S. This letter was finished on 11/26/61. Would you please let
Spencer, your grandson, know the news I just wrote you so I don’t have to write it twice. I have a short note for him enclosed. Thank you.
/Stapled on small note paper:/
Dear Mr. Heath –
Thank you for your various mailings to us including your parliamentary rules, the various pamphlets, the E.C. Riegel literature, and the book by Davidson. It was most kind of you to send all these things to us and they are most welcome.
Best wishes.
/s/ Joseph
Joseph A. Galambos
______________________________________________________________________
Letter to Heath and MacCallum at 312 Halesworth, Santa Ana,
California, from Andrew J. Galambos, director, Free Enterprise
Institute, PO Box 22189, Los Angeles 22, California
March 21, 1962
Dear Mr. Heath and Mr. MacCallum;
We are expecting you at the Blair House this Saturday, March 24, 1962 to commence the course, “Property and Its Productive Administration” (Course 1005 of the Free Enterprise Institute). The scheduled hours for the class are 1:30 p.m. to 4:30 p.m. The course is scheduled for six Saturday afternoon sessions beginning with March 24th and concluding with April 23th. If you desire and are able to continue, we are willing to extend the course two further sessions to May 5th and 12th respectively. However, we have billed the course as a six session one with our enrollees.
The location of Blair House is 445 North Rossmore, Los Angeles. Rossmore is the southern extension of Vine Street and the Blair House lies about l¼ miles south of Sunset Blvd. and Vine Street and about the same distance north of Wilshire Blvd. and Rossmore. The course will meet in the Colonial Room on the second floor (there is an elevator). The course will meet in this room all but one of these sessions; the third session will be located elsewhere (to be announced) because this room is not available that date.
We hope the contract will be prepared by Saturday. In any event the terms are as we stated it to both of you orally and we are operating with this understanding as an oral contract to be superseded by the written one.
We are remunerating you for your lectures 25% of the gross tuition we collect ($30 for the course) plus the same percentage of guest fees (if any)($6 per person per session). In addition, we are paying 6¼% additional fee to you of the gross tuition and guest fees received by us because this is an original course by you presented through the Free Enterprise Institute originally. We realize that this fee will not make you rich – but at least we are operating compatibly with the principle that services rendered are paid for. Your larger profit (as ours) is ideological. It will enable you to create a new book beyond Citadel, Market and Altar with less effort than otherwise and it will enable you to preserve these ideas (which we feel are worth preserving).
Further terms include the retention of the tapes of your lectures by us and permission to use them for future playing subject to a 10% royalty to you for all moneys we collect, if any, plus a 2½% override as an original course (total 12½% for playing of the tapes).
We will also provide you with a copy of the tapes for your use in editing them to convert the material into a book. We further state that in the event you are not able to edit these tapes into a book that Mr. MacCallum can do so in your place or that the undersigned and/or Alvin Lowi can do so in the event Mr. MacCallum cannot do so either. Furthermore, the Free Enterprise Institute and a publishing company to be affiliated with it will have sole publication rights of such book to emanate from this course (not only will this be of benefit to us, but it will better insure that the book will be published at all commercially, ultimately).
We also are putting republication of CMA into the contract as a future effort on our part which you will authorize.
The lecture and override fees (total 31¼%) is to be on the actual moneys collected as tuition and guest fees(if any). In addition to tuition-paying enrollees there will be the following people taking the course without tuition;
Joseph A. Galambos
Suzanne J. Galambos
Alvin Lowi, Jr.
Billy A. Robbins
Donald H. Allen
Konda L. Allen
Donald Smelick
Spencer MacCallum.
These people are all in attendance for the convenience of the Institute. The first four are staff members and faculty of the Institute and Institute policy is to admit all faculty without tuition to other courses offered during the tenure of such position; this means, incidentally, that at the completion of Course 1003 by you, Mr. Heath, you will be entitled to a refund of the tuition you paid on Course 100 (in today’s corrupt society this would be called a fringe benefit). Mr. and Mrs. Allen will be there for our convenience to handle the book displays for our affiliate, The CCI Bookshelf. Mr. MacCallum will be present as a service to the Institute and yourself in providing assistance to you Mr. Heath. Mr. Smelick will be present for other reasons for the Institute. Although he will not pay tuition to us, we will pay you a percentage on him as though he were paying tuition because his services are not to you but to us.
We do not expect a large class for you, but we do expect an interested one. We could have been able to provide you up to 50 enrollees in the summer. However, because of your indefinite plans about this summer and personal circumstances we felt that it would be better to offer the course now definitely than in the summer with less certainty.
I know that several of our prospective enrollees for the summer will, for various reasons, not be able to take it now. But we already do have sufficient enrollees that you will have your time well-rewarded. The ultimate profit to both of us, I think you will agree, is the permanent preservation of your ideas. We consider your course is a long-term investment in better ideas about our emerging society (your admirable expression).
We are very pleased and honored to have you join our faculty and be the first one to offer a course for us other than Course 100, our original and basic course. As you know, we will be offering three other courses this year (Courses 1001 – von Mises, 1002 – Read, and 76 – Galambos); we are delighted yours is the first new one.
Mrs. Manning has objected to our referring to you as “Professor” in our announcement. She did not understand our intent; possibly you didn’t either. We did net claim you are a professor from elsewhere (as von Mises is). We called you that because this Institute is of university stature (and then some) and we called you that because you are giving a guest course for us. Under the circumstances, consider yourself appointed Guest Professor. It is not outside accreditation, but content of courses that determine academic attainment. We consider ourselves fully competent to make this appointment.
This letter is not a contract in the legal sense, but it is one in the moral sense. Our contract is oral at the moment and contains these points already. I have jotted them down in writing that there be no misunderstanding about what I said and you have knowledge of our intent and recollection of what I have said orally – which you accepted. This will be followed by a written contract incorporating these ideas in legal terminology as drawn up by Mr. Robbins.
We hope this relationship will be satisfying to you and of long-term profit to you as well as us.
With kindest regards and best wishes,
Respectfully,
|
/s/ Joseph A. Galambos
P.S. This was addressed to you too Mr. MacCallum in your capacity as being your Grandfather’s assistant as well as intellectual heir.
_______________________________________________________________
Pencil draft for note to Joseph A. Galambos
March 23, 1962?
Extreme anxiety neurosis plus sanitary insecurity have made
it impossible for me to give course. This is the greatest disappointment of my long life. I am well assured of your nationwide success.
Spencer Heath
_______________________________________________________________
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 3077
Commentary by Alvin Lowi on Galambos
February 14, 2002
Property, according to Spencer Heath, is anything that can become the subject matter of contract. Heath didn’t try to incorporate morality into his definition. Locke and Galambos, on the other hand, each started out by saying that an individual owns himself, and went from there to justify the ownership of other things (except, as we have seen land and natural resources). Although optimally each individual does own himself, it can easily be observed that most societies condone the practice of slavery. Heath predicted that those societies that most condoned slavery would be the least progressive in terms of life-years.
To be useful, a definition is descriptive of something. For Heath, “property” describes one way in which people interact with respect to scarce resources. It describes a kind of observable behavior. He doesn’t start with a moral premise that “man owns himself” and then build from there. A normative statement is not a definition; we shouldn’t confuse it with a natural science, descriptive approach to understanding social behavior. Galambos’ so-called definition is really a moral prescription and has nothing to do with observed behavior. What Galambos is saying is that people should everywhere have exclusive jurisdiction over themselves. He is certainly not observing that they everywhere do, since people clearly do not everywhere own themselves. As a matter of fact, we observe the opposite. While none but small pockets of chattel slavery remain in the world, national governments everywhere enslave their populations. Each year, they tell them how much of their product they may keep, and it is almost universally deemed legitimate that they should hold the power of life or death over any who resist. Galambos’ is a rallying cry against the perceived injustice of government just as Locke’s was in resisting the king in the 17th century. Neither is describing social or any other observed natural phenomena. As reporters, they are utterly untrue to the facts.
SH proposed the unit of “man years.” He predicted that where two populations are equal in numbers by census count but vary significantly in terms of man-years, this difference would correlate with a difference in economic liberty. In general terms, anything conducive to greater man-years in the population is social, and the reverse is anti-social. It was in this light that he examined all institutions–art, science, politics.
It’s commonly said that man is born free. He is not. Freedom is both learned and earned. Freedom is the extent of one’s options, the breadth of one’s ability, and that is determined primarily by one’s technical expertise and knowledge–of which we have very little if any at birth. Ignorance is the chief limitation upon our freedom. It can be argued that it is not the only limitation, since restraints can be imposed by other people or circumstances. Even there, however, knowledge is determinant–knowledge how to nullify or evade such restraint or turn it to advantage. The condition characterized by absence of restraint by others is called liberty. Although the two words are often used interchangeably, liberty is a very minor sub-category of freedom. As compared with ignorance, tyranny is a comparatively minor limitation on our freedom. It only looms large because we chafe under it. When we say that freedom is earned as well as learned or discovered, we mean not only that we earn it by the conscientious exercise of our mental faculties, but by conscientiously serving others in ways that in turn prompt them to serve us. That makes both better off than before the exchange and hence more free. Each has earned an increment of freedom by freely exchanging goods or services with another.
_______________________________________________________________
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 3078
Letter from Alvin Lowi Jr. to Ted Marshall with biographical
and other data on himself, Spencer Heath, and Andrew J. Galambos
February 28, 2008
Dear Ted:
Attach my bio in your format. Got to rambling a bit because this is the first time I have ever tried to write out this part of my history. Tried to send it last week without success. Trying again reformatted. Hope you can open it and download it this time.
I have written some other essays that may help fill in some blanks on the history of FEI and a couple of the key ideas that I believe distinguished Galambos’ teachings. There is an autobio entitled “A Lasting Encounter” written in 2003 for Prof. Walter Block of Loyola Univ. New Orleans and the Mises Institute for inclusion in an autobiographical archive maintained at the LewRockwell.com web site about the experiences of people discovering freedom. This archive is a collection of personal histories of libertarians regarding their awakening to the ideas. They are written along the lines of Jerome Tuccille’s “It All Began With Ayn Rand.” In my case, it was not libertarianism but liberalism, and my ideological history began with Andrew Galambos, not Ayn Rand. Incidentally, Jerome Tucille was no friend of Galambos.
I wrote other essays to explain how I sorted out the myth of political omniscience and discovered the grand alternative political government in the course of my Galambos understudy. These items are still in draft condition and would benefit from critical review. The titles are “Experience with Galambos the Author,” “Government as a Marketable Service,” “Must We Depend on Political Protection? (with Apologies to Robert LeFevre),” and “The Entrepreneurial Corporation.”
The most important debt I owe to Galambos is an understanding and appreciation of science, which I have tried to memorialize as “Scientific Method: In Search of Legitimate Authority in Society.” As you know, I have been working on this project for some years now and am up to Version IX going on X. I think you have Version I. That this work is unfinished is evidenced by Jay Snelson’s 100-pages of comments derived from his review of Version VIII.
It goes without saying that I welcome your comments and questions on my musings. You had a lot to do with getting me to write out my remembrances of my times with Galambos and FEI. I long hesitated to do so because, like most of the FEI graduates, I deferred to Galambos’ priority to get his ideas into print without adding to his distractions. Waiting thirty years for SIAA was an inordinate amount of time for deference. Still, there is as much yet to come with little or no prospect of realization. When does deference become indulgence? Oblivion?
Please pass on these sentiments to your Volitionist circle. I look forward to their comments also.
See you April 10 at the Shenandoah. Put me down for the fried chicken. A check for $20.00 payable to you is in the mail.
Best regards,
Alvin
BIO FOR TED MARSHALL’S COLLECTION:
Alvin Lowi, Jr.
Born in Gadsden, Alabama, July 21, 1929.
Graduated high school in 1947 and left Gadsden to enter NROTC at Georgia Tech in Atlanta.
First came to California in June, 1948, as a Midshipman, USNR. Reported for duty on the light cruiser USS Astoria then moored at the San Francisco Embarcadero.
Received bachelor’s degree in mechanical engineering and commission in USN from Georgia Tech in June, 1951. Reported for active duty soon afterward on the amphibious assault transport USS Cavalier APA 37 steaming off eastern shore of Hokkaido, Japan.
Stricken with infectious hepatitis aboard ship in 1952, I was shipped to the Great Lakes Naval Hospital for treatment and convalescence. While in confinement, I read Thomas Paine’s “Age of Reason” and Ayn Rand’s “The Fountainhead.” I recovered from infectious hepatitis but not from infectious individualism. Reassigned to the Pacific Fleet via Navy Diesel School in December, 1952, I reported to the USS LSM 236 in San Diego as chief engineer destined for duty again in the Western Pacific Theatre of operations. In January, 1954, this ship was given to the French Navy for service in the Indo China War, whereupon I resigned my regular Navy commission. I was discharged from active duty in June, 1954, to return to civilian life and the study of engineering at Georgia Tech in Atlanta in the fall of 1954.
Completing graduate work in mechanical engineering at Georgia Tech I turned in my masters thesis in December, 1955, and departed Atlanta to return to California for the third time. Hired by the Garrett Corporation in Westchester as a preliminary design engineer, I was involved in the design of aircraft cabin pressure and air conditioning systems. Meanwhile, I enrolled in UCLA Extension for further graduate study.
I left Garrett Corp. in 1958 to continue graduate studies as regular student in engineering at UCLA. Offered a scholarship, I joined the technical staff of Ramo-Wooldridge Corp. around the block from Garrett to work on ballistic missile design. There I met Andrew Galambos. He occupied the adjacent office and was the member of the technical staff trusted to calculate the trajectory of the missiles I helped design. I also met Don Allen there. His job as a technical staff member was to program Galambos’ trajectory calculations on the mainframe computer. Allen was also Galambos’ partner in the insurance and securities business they were running on the side. I became a client and close friend. Galambos tutored me in thermodynamics among other things. Together, we three hatched the Free Enterprise Institute as a scheme to promote Galambos’ enthralling lectures on the subjects of science, astronomy, history, capitalism, personal financial security and freedom, which he was giving gratis at lunch-time every day in the cafeteria to whoever wanted to listen. Many did so because the Soviets had just launched “Sputnik” and few had any idea how such space flight was possible. Also, the communist threat from Moscow was palpable, never mind the socialist threat from Washington and Sacramento.
Ramo-Wooldridge merged with Thompson Products in 1959 to form TRW. Galambos quit soon thereafter over management’s rejection of his proposal to form and execute a commercial astronautics venture. He then joined the faculty of Whittier college but continued to work on building his own school, the Free Enterprise Institute. This project kept us in contact. Meanwhile, the part of TRW we worked for was seized by the Air Force and set up as a public trust institution with a single customer to be called the Aerospace Corporation.
Galambos despaired the world would be safe for astrophysicists, especially those like him. He resolved to do something about that and asked me to join in the effort. The Liberal Incorporated was organized with me as a director in 1959. The Free Enterprise Institute was subsequently formed as a wholly owned subsidiary.
In 1959, Galambos infected me with his infatuation with Barry Goldwater as a prospective President of the United States. He cozied up with members of Californians for Goldwater, whom he considered good prospects for his course. He also sold a lot of copies of Goldwater’s book off the shelf of Poor Richard’s bookstore in Hollywood, which attracted the owner’s support for the course.
But the political campaign became a distraction. It took Galambos to the 1960 Republican National Convention in Chicago where he met Goldwater and declared “Nominate anyone you please. I’m voting for Barry Goldwater.” After the convention, he wrote off both Goldwater and the Republicans and set off to New York to find out if he could ally with some kindred spirits and minds in the freedom business, such as Ayn Rand, Ludwig von Mises and Henry Hazlitt. I drove with him to New York City in the fall of 1960 to help him break the ice.
Galambos returned from New York after Kennedy was elected with a plan to promote “Capitalism: the Key to Survival,” the first offering of the Free Enterprise Institute as Course 100. The following spring (1961), Galambos rented a room in the Hollywood Knickerbocker Hotel and started soliciting enrollments at a ridiculously low tuition. I was his unpaid staff assistant. Don Allen set up a book stall in the classroom each week and took orders. Peter Fleming, Chuck and Mary Estes, Billy Robbins, John and Muriel Platt, were among the twenty or so intense enrollees, who were excited to discover the alternative to communism. It was an exhilarating experience.
Galambos persuaded me and Billy Robbins to prepare and teach this course the following Fall, (1961) in other locations. I rounded up some backing from Peter Fleming and my Aerospace Corp. colleague Peter Bos and rented the back room in a bar at the Torrance Airport near my home. Peter Fleming was my first staff assistant. The Torrance class included Bos, Art and Ann Sperry, George and Lois Haddad, John Goode, Bob Calvert, John and Kirt Fenner, Arnold and Francine White, Carole Little, Cliff Wright, John and Maxine Cochran, Dolly Westerholm, Eleanor Weeks and others I can’t remember. The following Spring, 1962, Peter Fleming and Chuck Estes persuaded me to give the course in Santa Monica, which was done in a conference room rented at the Miramar Hotel. Among the attendees were Dick and Mimi Nesbit, Leroy and Shirley Taft, Phil and Patty Backer, Jack Carpenter, Lloyd Licher, Richard Grant, Don and Riki Balluck, Harry Browne, Jay Snelson, Polly and Paul Nielsen, Martin Fenton, Spencer MacCallum, Harlan Carr and others. It is difficult to remember who was enrolled in Santa Monica because of its proximity to the Valley where Robbins was lecturing and to Hollywood where Galambos was lecturing, and given the unlimited exchange privileges offered at the time.
Inspired by Galambos’ teachings, I started my own engineering business in 1962 and undertook to develop, manufacture and market an invention of my own for a change. With a young family to support and qualifying exams to prepare for and no way to suspend the clock and calendar, something had to give. I could not satisfy Galambos’ demand to prepare and teach more courses, and could not deny my ambition to be in business for myself. So I took the entrepreneurial path taught by Galambos and recruited Jay Snelson, Dick Nesbit, George Haddad and Harry Browne to pick up the FEI lecturing and mentoring baton and promoted their candidacy to Galambos accordingly. By 1965, I had replaced myself as an FEI lecturer in two locations and added three more. Meanwhile, Galambos had replaced Course 100 with Snelson’s more popular version designated V-50, and he introduced a new course V-201, which I attended and prepared to teach as a substitute for Galambos if necessary. I then (1966) quit Aerospace employment and wage slavery for good. I haven’t had a job since.
In the interim, I prepared a prospectus for a book publication venture designed to get a limited edition of Galambos’ Course 100 into print. I lined up $500,000 in subscriptions from about 30 people on the strength of my proposal to work with Galambos on a definite schedule and budget using available notes and tapes to compile, edit and print a limited number (100 was the original figure) of serialized copies of a printed compendium well-edited, indexed and bound. I had already prepared a table of contents, which Galambos admired, and I had in my possession a well-criticized set of lectures on tape (his and mine), which he considered worthy of transcription if necessary.
By the time I was able to arrange and present my formal proposal to Galambos in the presence of the subscribers in Galambos’ offices on East Beverly Blvd., Monterey Park (1964), some of them had already begun to bid up the ante for participation in the project. Apparently, low-numbered copies of the book were deemed more valuable and premiums were being offered to gain priority for obtaining them. This auction resulted in an escalation of the initial offering price of the book. Galambos got cold feed and vetoed my proposal. Fortunately, there had been no money transactions.
After Spencer Heath died in 1963, my friend Spencer MacCallum asked me to help him sort out his grandfather’s unpublished writings, particularly those that pertained to aeronautics, engineering, physics and philosophy of science. I was interested in Heath’s work based on personal acquaintance and considered this activity to be complementary to my research for FEI because Heath’s “Socionomy” was consistent with Galambos’ “Volitional Science,” and, but for failing health, Heath would have given a course on the subject for FEI in 1962. My report on this work entitled “Survey and Review of the Physical Science Inquiries of Spencer Heath” was published by The Heather Foundation (aka Spencer Heath MacCallum) in 1966. It contained a generous and elaborate acknowledgement to Andrew J. Galambos, which was most appropriate inasmuch as I had employed scientific insights learned from Galambos in accomplishing the work. Nevertherless, Galambos was displeased and refused to accept a copy of the bound document as a token of my appreciation.
I remained involved in FEI and LIONS Tech affairs as a research associate and back-up lecturer until 1969 when Galambos asked me to resign. The ostensible reason was that I could not give Galambos’ ideological program the priority he demanded. We disagreed on the question of which comes first, science or ideology. He asked me to disclaim proprietary rights to any innovation contained in his courses while, at the same time, tendered me a check for $500.00 as a “down payment” on accrued royalties. Our parting was amiable. I agreed to an unlimited license to any innovation attributable to me and to an abstention from any ideological activities that would tend to confuse, disparage or compete with him and his program. For me, this commitment was like Br’er Rabbits’ to the brier patch.
I continued to work with Spencer MacCallum on his grandfather’s literary estate. I consulted with Spencer on his book “Art of Community” published by the Institute for Humane Studies in 1970. After Galambos bought and sold all the copies of Heath’s book “Citadel, Market and Altar,” I worked with MacCallum to bring to print a new and expanded second edition for which I wrote a lengthy foreword. The second edition has not yet materialized but my foreword was finally published as “The Legacy of Spencer Heath: A Former Student Remembers the Man and Offers Some Observations on the Scientific Orientation of His Work,” Heather Foundation, July, 1998.
During the early 1970’s, I participated in several seminars at F.A. Harper’s Institute for Humane Studies in Menlo Park, CA. My concentration was on the scientific basis of Austrian economics.
During the 1980’s, I participated in a study group organized by Robert LeFevre called “The Seekers.” This group included Chuck Estes, Spencer MacCallum, Dick Nesbit, Butler Shaffer, Bruce Canter, Jack Pugsley, Ken Gregg and Jim Bennett. LeFevre was intrigued with the question “How do you know you are right?” and regretted he never had the opportunity hear Galambos’ answer.
I kept in touch with Jay Snelson over the intervening years. We collaborated on what we both considered to be Galambos’ most important gift to us, namely an understanding and appreciation of scientific epistemology and method especially as possibly applied to social phenomena. Our exchanges of correspondence on the subject led to my draft of “Scientific Method: In Search of Legitimate Authority in Society” in 1996. This was my first direct experience using a personal computer for word processing.
I had managed to refrain from any freedom-oriented ideological activities sanctioned by Galambos until Harry Browne asked me to critique a recollection of Galambos he was writing for publication in Liberty Magazine. About the same time (1997), I met Ted Marshall through Jay Snelson in a quest to retrieve some property from the Galambos estate. His friendship with Galambos and my friendship with both encouraged me to memorialize my experiences with Galambos and FEI well as to document my own ideas of the world as I have come to see them. A number of such items can be found on my computer hard drive as well as on the web at LewRockwell.com, Above-the-Garage.com, EconomicGovernment.com, League-of-non-voters.org., the Adam Ferguson Institute and the Institute for Socionomic Research. To access some of these items on the internet, just go to Google, enter “Alvin Lowi, Jr” and search the links.
Ted also introduced me to his “Volitionist Circle,” a group of students of Galambos who occasionally meet for lunch at the Shenandoah (formerly Jabberwocky) in Los Alamitos to reminisce about the intellectual adventures with the FEI. I have enjoyed stimulating e-mail exchanges with members of the circle including Ted Marshall, Colin Marshall, Larry Grannis, Joseph Droll and Brian Gladish. More recently, I joined the Clarke-Willson’s Volitional Science Group at YahooGroups.com where I am the senior scholar. I was also invited to join the Libertarian Forum at GoogleGroups.com as the token Galambosian. My participation here has helped balance the Wikipedia article on Andrew Galambos.
______________________________________________________________
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 3077
Article by Alvin Lowi
April, 2008
SCIENCE VERSUS IDEOLOGY
Alvin Lowi, Jr.
April 11, 1998
Revised April, 2008
BACKGROUND
Andrew Joseph Galambos, founder of the Free Enterprise Institute (FEI) and The Liberal, Inc., is credited with the formulation of both a scientific and an ideological approach to advancing human freedom. He realized that significant social progress would require substantial change in public attitudes regarding politics and government, which, in turn, would require the successful propagation of an appropriate ideology or system of beliefs. But Galambos was aware that an appropriate ideology required solid scientific support to remain relevant to purpose in actuality.
It was on this basis that Galambos originally ventured to develop a university, ultimately to be known as the Liberal Institute of Natural Science and Technology (“LIONS Tech”). This was the vision that brought him his initial following (circa 1960) including this writer. Subsequently, he established FEI for the purpose of presenting assorted lecture courses to the public. The curriculum would be comprised primarily of courses of his own design and content, but complementary ones would be offered on occasion by notable free-market scholars and philosophers by invitation. FEI courses were designed primarily for lay adults having no specific preparation or prerequisites other than intellectual honesty. It was significant that the first 13-week course he offered was titled “Capitalism, the Key to Survival.”
Galambos believed an authentic social science was essential for making any real progress toward a more autonomous (“free”) society because science is the only known antidote for dogma, fantasy and superstition, human foibles that interfere with dealing with the world and life as it actually is, not as it “ought” to be. He taught science as the only check there is on arbitrary opinion.1 Moreover, he treated social advancement as a technological development based on a dependable social technology that derived from an authentic social science. The science was prerequisite.
Since predispositions of thought are the main obstacles to ideological enlightenment, which is the precursor to advancements in the art of social living, Galambos proposed a “Science of Volition” that could provide the theoretical foundation for his ideology of freedom, which he called “twenty-first-century liberalism.” Although he was mindful that the term “liberalism” had become a synonym for political conquest and socialism, he insisted on using that term as an appropriate label for his ideological program because it was traceable to its original nineteenth-century European meaning, which was individual liberty.2 He also claimed to have formulated the applicable science based on a unique set of postulates consistent with the American Revolution.3
Galambos’ recognized at the outset that as a social movement, his ideological program for “liberalism” (meaning laissez faire capitalism) owned a superficial resemblance to Karl Marx’s campaign for “scientific socialism” launched over 100 years earlier when these ideological labels were sharply differentiated in the public mind.4 However, Galambos, the professor of astrophysics and consultant to the aerospace industry, had an advantage over Marx, the unemployed lawyer and rabble-rouser. When it came to science, Galambos knew whereof he spoke. He was mindful of a fact of nature that the means employed for whatever purpose must be consistent with the ends sought and that both must conform to the dictates of nature as best they can be comprehended. He was under no illusions that nature could be second-guessed or subjected to conquest no matter the public clamor for such.
GALAMBOS VERSUS MARX
Curiously, both Marx and Galambos were innovators who claimed their approaches to the exposition of human social life were scientifically justified and that their wholly opposite means would attain precisely identical social ends, namely human freedom. The question immediately arises as to which of these starkly contrasting ideologies is the more authentic and realistic in the long run?
Until the relatively recent demise of the 75 year old Soviet Socialist Empire, few would have embraced Galambos’ views over Marx’s. Yet, Galambos had impeccable scientific credentials as well as solid evidence for advancing his hypotheses. Marx had none, but he made up for his deficiencies with ample fancy and chutzpah. Apparently, when it came to public promotion, Marx’s appeal to vanity gave him a short-term advantage. The longer term consequences would not become apparent to scientific observation for over a generation. Even then, life would afford only so much leisure.
Fundamentally, Galambos believed that the best humans could attain in the world would be harmonious accommodation with the nature of the world as it is, which is to be obtained only through scientific understanding. Accordingly, after a brief flirtation with the “Goldwater-for-President” movement at the Republican National Convention in 1960, he abandoned political participation of any kind, concentrating on the purely social phenomena that endure from generation to generation without conflict.
By contrast, Karl Marx postulated the existence of social classes in perpetual conflict that would remain so until all the classes were forcefully merged into a uniform class of survivors, the most numerous class, which he labeled the “proletariat.”* Marx’s “science” established that this result could only be accomplished by force since the privileges and wealth characterizing the minority privileged “classes” would never abandon their privileges voluntarily. Marx also understood that the most numerous class could be incited to riot over envy of the more wealthy, a battle they would win by sheer force of numbers. Accordingly, he developed and promoted an ideological program of political action to foment and intensify “class” conflict as a prelude to the expropriation of the “bourgeoisie” (middle class, merchants or business people) and forceful regimentation of the “proletariat” (“lower-class” laborers or wage-earners).4 Marx thus advocated “class” warfare where the classes were arbitrary or statistical demographic artifacts constructed to purpose. His program had ideological appeal because the vast majority were inclined to envy the few holders of wealth and could be enticed to encroach once convinced of the right.
Marx had no familiarity with science as that endeavor had come to be known from the works of the likes of Galileo and Newton. His expertise was superficial at best and strictly rhetorical. He was a scientist in name only, the term “science” having been introduced into the English language as recently as 1833 by William Whewell.
Nevertheless, Marx’s approach was highly relevant to and opportunistic for the attainment of political ends, as the modern history of national governments will attest. In that sense, Marx could be considered a political scientist with at least as much of a claim to the title as Nicolo Machiavelli, who’s ______ is indubitable. We are here defining political science as the science of human conquest by humans.
Marx’s stated political objective was to create a classless society by what he claimed to be scientific means. Although his claims to social science were purely rhetorical, his political science was realistic insofar as he was offering expeditious and opportunistic means to attain the ends he sought. His approach was totally collectivistic and coercive yet appealing to base human emotions, showing those more vicious than he how to exploit peoples’ susceptibility to greed, envy and vanity. Since Marx’s objective was “the dictatorship of the proletariat,” the coercive means he advocated were quite consistent with his ends.
GALAMBOS’ APPROACH
Galambos’ ideology works out to be the exact antithesis of Marx’s. He treated humanity as a population of volitional, autonomous and sentient individuals, each of whom owned his life and all the derivatives of that life. Whereas Marx favored persons of need over those of ability, Galambos’ treated all persons alike, equal in moral standing. He considered every person sovereign over his own estate, that each is an owner regardless of the amount of property in his possession, property being his life and all of its proper derivatives. He appealed to human rationality and individual self-esteem and he was uncompromisingly individualistic and volitional in his approach. He had no use for “classes.”
As a scientist, Galambos knew that, regardless of what people believe, nature (including those very people) will prevail in the end. He also knew that the popularity of an ideology only affects the rate of change toward whatever ends sought, realistic or otherwise. Only science can illuminate realistic objectives. So the ideology must be consistent with if not actually subservient to the pertinent scientific theory or else the momentum of change might well be in the wrong direction. To ensure his approach was realistic in the long run, Galambos gave priority to the use of scientific method over all other considerations. Characteristically, he always led off his courses with the question “How do you know you are right?” He then fashioned an approach to social change based on his apprehension of humanity as he found it emphasizing scientific and technological development because those subjects were less tainted with propaganda. He relied on science to reveal how human society works to the extent that it does, finding self-interest, an enduring trait of humanity, to be his ally rather than his nemesis. He found support for his hypothesis in the “pursuit of happiness” clause in the Declaration of Independence. And he discovered that the beauty of laissez capitalism is not that it encourages human greed but that it renders it harmless if not actually creative and productive, from which he taught that to profit is moral and it is moral to seek profit.
A TURN OF MIND
As he made progress in scientific terms, Galambos would find out and point to what was the “right” as it pertains to social phenomena. Among those conclusions he would also point out what might be termed “moral” and “ethical” as those terms have come to classify human behavior in terms of its effect on peace and tranquility in the neighborhood. The quality and quantity of this body of “knowledge” would be the basis of his ideology. Although intellectual honesty is a rare commodity, Galambos’ approach struck a nerve with a sufficient number of like-minded individuals to make a market for his lectures on the subject.
However, inasmuch as science does not produce results CERTAIN, science could not readily satisfy Galambos’ quest for an “absolute morality,” a quest that became more compelling as he struggled to make his ideology more alluring to the public. Since popularity could accelerate progress as he envisioned it in ideological terms, he was soon persuaded to stake a claim to this moral high-ground to facilitate the attraction of those persons who were seeking definite and simple answers to the poignant and sometimes ambiguous social problems in evidence, which were often threatening to humanity and inhibitive of social progress as they saw it. This turn of mind toward definite answers to specific dilemmas was initially a marketing decision, but inasmuch as it received an enthusiastic response from his market, it became the predominant feature of his program from then on. It also imparted a decidedly “righteous” character to his campaign which tended to squelch skepticism thereby strengthening the ideology at the expense of the science.
When Galambos assumed he already knew what is universally “moral,” or at least “immoral,” without first accrediting such a conclusion through scientific procedures, he justified a third and overriding criterion of “rightness” that was outside the scope of traditional scientific deliberations. This special or ad hoc criterion he considered relevant only to social phenomena. This was certainly a novel idea in the annals of science. However, it introduced unfamiliar epistemological issues in the process. While such a postulate no doubt boosted the potency of his ideological appeal and simplified his ideological approach, it severely compromised his scientific position as regards society inasmuch as it arbitrarily set aside social phenomena as something extra-natural. To say the least, it was premature to introduce “absolute morality” (meaning universal morality) into an ideology as long as the underlying science was immature on the question. For example, a good deal of ambiguity yet remains to be resolved on the question of intellectual proprietorship notwithstanding Galambos’ “Theory of Primary Property.”7
Galambos himself had explained the impropriety of giving priority to ideology over science when he contrasted Milliken’s “electron discovery” with Ehrenhaft’s microcoulomb research. He pointed out how Milliken postulated his answer based on his ideological belief in Lorenz’s electron theory, namely that “there is an electron and I’m going to measure its charge.” He then fitted his crude oil-drop data to support his hypothesis. He got the Nobel Prize for his cleverness, not for his science.
Galambos admired Ehrenhaft’s truly scientific approach to the question. He would explore the domain of small electrical charges to look for the existence of a particular one called the electron. Ehrenhaft meticulously measured diminishingly small electrical charges with great precision as they were found to occur in nature. As a result, he discovered that among all the small electrical charges extant, there appeared a prominent population of charges having the value of Milliken’s “electron.” Thus, it was really Ehrenhaft who corroborated Lorenz’s hypothesis and, in doing so, he extended the frontier of knowledge of all electronic phenomena. Milliken’s work was finished when he got Nobel recognition whereas Ehrenhaft’s was just beginning.
His story of the electron discovery would recall for Galambos one of Eddington’s about the “ichthyologist’s net,” illustrating how epistemological problems arise when the means employed for the research are inconsistent with the conclusions to be supported.8 More importantly, the selectively subjective nature of knowledge according to Eddington was revealed in which a seed of doubt always remains about the immutable universe regardless of the excellence of the science.
SHIFTING EMPHASIS
It is curious that when Galambos attached such terms as “absolute rightness” to his social conclusions, he broke faith with Eddington’s advice. Yet, by his own admission, Galambos put the cart before the horse when he implemented an ideological program irrespective of its underlying scientific basis — especially its epistemology.
When Galambos decided to make FEI an ideological venture, he put research and literature on the back burner where they would be less likely distract his market with too many questions to confront and air out in public. By that time (1964), Galambos was confident in his knowledge and anxious to get on with “building” a free society. A divergence of views developed on this matter, not least the very idea of building society by human design. Some in the community of FEI students argued out of engineering habit that the research must be done up front in order to get the program “right” the first time out. Others saw no problem with the promotion of abstract idealism as long as nature was to be depended on to take its mysterious course — in other words, let the “market” decide. There was nothing essentially antagonistic in these contending viewpoints since both were valid in their respective contexts and no compulsion was involved. However, Galambos had come to believe he did not have time to first advance the science before promoting belief in and practice of those certain new institutions that he was convinced would be confirmed by experience. He was impatient to reduce them to practice himself regardless of the maturity of his know-how or of the market demand for such. He was frustrated in the knowledge that growth in the social know-how of the individual would pace the evolution of the social structure toward the ideal he envisioned regardless of the urgency of the global situation or the eloquence of the ideological appeal. He convinced himself and many others that his “technology” was a fait accompli. But as of the time of his death in 1997, there was little evidence extant to support his claim.
For some, Galambos’ emphasis on moralistic notions seemed anachronistic, conceited and arrogant. His high-minded ideological manner suggested that a kind of aristocratic authority had crept into his program. In addition, he began to exhibit signs of obsession with visions of immortality. In retrospect, it is fortunate the roles were not reversed between him and his students because no one was equipped to take his place in his ideological program, which was inspirational by all accounts. At the same time, Galambos made his skeptics place more meaningful even if they were on the outside looking in.
An attractive and persuasive feature of Galambos’ approach was a glossary of cogent and precise definitions of the key words he employed in constructing his theory. In this glossary, he exemplified the virtues of science in giving specific, unambiguous meaning to the key words he would be relying on to proceed with his development. The word “absolute” is a case in point. Among dozens of meanings listed in the lexicon of common usage, Galambos adopted the one from physics, namely that “an absolute is independent of arbitrary standards of determination.” This definition would serve as a reminder of the importance of “operationalizing” the definitions of other key words to the greatest extent possible to provide instruction as to how anyone can make the determination for himself.9 In taking this approach, Galambos sought to demonstrate to others how science, particularly physics, had become the powerfully useful discipline that it is in acquiring reliable new knowledge of the world.
CHALLENGING DEFINITIONS
Ideologically, the only grounds for arguing with Galambos’ definitions are internal or logical consistency in HIS argument. Since it was after all HIS theory and he had long labored over such problems early in his program, it would be very difficult for even the most conscientious student to find fault. Such scrutiny has been made even more challenging by the fact that Galambos left little written material open for study. That arguments remain in making precise settlements of ownership issues under some important circumstances is evidence that refinements in his definitions are needed. But most of all, the test of Galambos’ theory of the social world would come from observational experience, just as he taught.
Galambos encountered a particularly vexatious problem of definition as he grappled with his concept of “absolute morality,” which he made the central feature of his ideology. The problem arises in attempting to operationalize the definition of the term “morality,” i.e. moral independent of arbitrary standards of determination. Since he retained the conventional polar notion of morality as a contest of “good” versus “evil” in human terms, he needed a more universal term with which to express moral distinctions precisely. He found such a tool in the word “property,” used in its singular sense that is traditional in economic, ethical, common-law and political deliberations wherein it is common to refer to “private property” as the province of the individual human being. As a result, he deprived himself of the utility of the term “property” in its plural, scientific sense referring to natural attributes having no moral connotation whatever but otherwise indispensable as tools in the scientific investigation of any province of natural phenomena. It is unfortunate that the singular usage would necessarily preempt the plural usage traditional in scientific endeavor. But the singular sense is consistent with traditional moral philosophy. At least his precise but non-scientific definition of “property” and its counterpart “plunder” would allow a coherent treatment of morality consistent with tradition. This was an important ideological consideration inasmuch as it aligned him with respectable philosophical antecedents like Moses, John Locke, Adam Smith and Frederic Bastiat.
Galambos encountered a logical circularity in his definition of property (the good) when he relied on a definition of what property is not, namely plunder (the bad). He defined plunder to be the result of coercion which he defined in turn as an intentional interference with property. So it was HIS problem to sort out what was and was not property on the basis of what was and was not a “moral” means of acquisition.
Since moral means could be observed (peaceful production) but immoral means could not (by virtue of the invisibility of intent in his definition of coercion), frustrations arose in applications of Galambos’ theory of morality. The question is not so much whether usurpation, trespass and harm can be observed to occur to one at the hand of another. The problem that remains in applying Galambos’ theory is to differentiate intent to harm from simple inadvertence or greed. Such a distinction is important if morality is to become more than a matter of arbitrary opinion and fulfill Galambos’ claim to the discovery of “absolute morality.”
Galambos never fully resolved this problem to anyone’s satisfaction including his own. Yet, he was obliged make moral judgments if only to demonstrate to his students how they should behave, at least toward him if not also toward others. Some have angrily reacted to this discrepancy in his theory as hypocrisy. Such a reaction is understandable since Galambos assumed such a high moral position. On the other hand, this discrepancy can be considered to be merely unfinished business and not just a hopelessly discrediting flaw, which he might have rectified had he lived longer.
As long as he was alive, such discrepancies were exclusively HIS business. Now that he is not, they are attached to his intellectual and literary estate about which many are in doubt as to how the subject matter will be administered and accessed. Any discrepancies in his definitions that lead to an ownership dilemma should be looked upon as a problem to be solved in his honor. After all, he gave us the property postulate and showed us how proprietary administration was the grand alternative to politics and bureaucracy.10 Where would we be now without these insights? The obverse of this question is “what can we do with them now?”
Some “true believers” fail to see any problem at all with Galambos’ definitions, which so neatly and elegantly satisfy their longing for order in experience that “minor” discrepancies are readily overlooked or tolerated considering the alternatives. They tend to regard all attempts to amend the definitions as grandstanding at Galambos’ expense. No doubt there will be some who will be just trying to stir up matters as self-serving gestures, safe enough now that Galambos is dead. However, some students are uninhibited in their inquiries as a result of having some precedence in the matter. A few can trace their concerns back to the origin of the problem in Galambos’ theory. Others may have acquired similar insights independently of Galambos. More recent FEI graduates who uncritically embrace Galambos’ ideology tend to be intellectually paralyzed as if his definitions were off-limits to inquiry, thus setting aside these issues as morally forbidden territory. Such a posture inclines them to condemn others still searching and to overlook Galambos’ more fundamental consideration never to waver from dedication to science. Therefore, Galambos’ students can be assured of the propriety of subjecting any definitions to a proper logical and observational test on the basis of scientific merit and on their own recognizance.
Important questions arise regarding Galambos’ definition of property and how to apply it. These questions seem to fall into two categories, one abstract and the other practical. Questions of the first type, illustrated above, relate to the strength of the logic underlying Galambos’ ideological program regardless of any scientific support for it. The second type has to do with operationalization for the purpose of facilitating the essential falsification step in the scientific method. Both types of questions must be answered in the course of any scientific advancement of the theory as required to support a practical and enduring social ideology.
Obviously, any definition that staggers application for fear of obscure moral consequences will be socially dysfunctional. After all, the only way one could be “absolutely” sure his actions would never raise a moral issue is to abstain from taking any initiative whatsoever. Without taking any action at risk of committing an “immoral” act, a person will soon find his most moral but utterly paralyzed life had become an unbearable misery not to be endured for long. Ultimately, all such “moral” persons will have ceased to contribute to the human gene pool, the evolution of the species thereby proceeding on the basis of more realistic human inclinations. It is a thoroughly medieval notion that there can be any essential conflict between morality and reality for the perfection of the species. If “heaven” can never be here on Earth to be experienced by diligent human beings, then “heaven” is merely an abstraction designed by the cunning to manipulate the gullible.
A refinement in Galambos’ definition of property must be made if only to strengthen his theoretical argument for human freedom or liberty as he defined those terms. In addition, the definition must be operationalized to facilitate reductions to practice in the real world to enhance human life and advance reliable and unambiguous (i.e. scientific) understanding of the process to make it more relevant and repeatable into the indefinite future. Since Galambos can no longer do this job for himself, it remains for others to take the risk of trying to do what he would have done eventually had he lived long enough. The main risk here is a short-run loss of ideological potency from a weakened (i.e. more tentative) moral argument. In the long run, this disadvantage will be more than offset by an invigorated scientific impetus leading to a more realistic and therefore strengthened concept of morality. Then, the absence of Galambos’ personal charisma will not be so critical to social progress.
Perhaps no more radical an amendment to Galambos’ definition of property is required than to simply drop any dependence on “non-coercion” and rely on what “volition” is all about. This achievement calls for some astute biological and psychological insight in order to be able to differentiate between mere animal behavior and uniquely human behavior. Perhaps also in this regard, even more should be made of Galambos’ integrity concept, but such a development is likely to stress individual competence and prudence — know-how and self-government — rather than avoidance of immorality and submission to restitution. True enough, this approach will soften the ideology but it will strengthen the theory for proceeding on to scientific and technological application. It might even result in liberating “Property” from its bondage to singular usage such that whatever property of humanity that term formerly stood for becomes one among many natural attributes to understand. Then, instead of postulating morality or a perfectly moral humanity as an ideal, a possibly unattainable state of affairs, we set about to find out what moral behavior consists of and how it can be practiced successfully in the real world. We already have a pretty good idea of this approach, thanks to Galambos, just like Milliken and Ehrenhaft did regarding the discovery of the electron thanks to Lorenz.
Operationalism challenges the definitions to provide instruction as to how to make observations regarding actual human behavior “independent of arbitrary standards of determination” in the pursuit of scientific inquiry. If not to actually make quantitative measurements with them, we have to be able to at least explain to each other how to look at the consequences of the definitions and come to unambiguous conclusions or non-contradictory identification. We can certainly learn how to observe conflict but it is doubtful that enough can be known to observe intent. Can psychology be trusted to rule on such a critical moral matter? This is where epistemology comes into play and psychology has a conflict of interest in the subject inasmuch as it purports to understand human behavior while claiming exclusive province over knowledge of human mental faculties.
THE FUTURE OF VOLITIONAL SCIENCE
Extrapolations from physics into the social domain are always hazardous but the analogy between the individualistic model of human social behavior and Planck’s quantum oscillator regarding electromagnetic radiative emission is enticing. For example, among all the “degrees of freedom” possessed by the quantum, the particular one that will be expressed in actuality (like a particular color of photonic light) will always satisfy the Principle of Least Action. That is all that can be inferred about the “intent” of the quantum. Likewise, at any given time, the human individual will express the particular one of his many possible options for action that fits into a least-action paradigm. Such a choice has been termed “the pursuit of happiness,” a characterization that offers no insight whatsoever into the nature of the specific intent behind it.
An interesting question is how Galambos’ “integrity of property principle” might be related to the principle of least action. If such a relationship can be established, it deserves to be called “Galambos’ Law” and that property of volitional beings now known as “Property” might be named the “galambosian” or some other term to distinguish it from the properties of volitional humanity in general. This practice would be consistent with the practices of physics, which regard mass, momentum, charge, position, etc. as distinguishable properties of the quantum. But it is the specific property known as the “Hamiltonian” that provides the greatest utility in ascertaining which of all possible courses of physical action is the most likely.11 The Hamiltonian is formulated in terms of “action,” not energy. In nature, action is minimized. Likewise, energy is conserved.
THE QUESTION OF JUSTICE
Forensic science has developed considerable confidence in the means for establishing responsibility for consequences on the basis of physical evidence. However, this profession can do little to prove intent. Thus, for any dispute adjudication to have a peaceful if not amicable outcome — an ideal of a “free society” — it cannot rely on retaliation based on a presumption of intent to injure. The beauty of Galambos (or possibly Estes’) restitution theory of justice is that it depends only on establishing responsibility regardless of the nature of the intent (if any) of those whose actions are connected with an injury to another. Also, only comparative responsibility is relevant since there is always a question of contributory negligence to consider. A theory of damages is yet another matter.
Few would argue that a person accused of causing injury to others is entitled to be judged solely on the facts of the consequences of his acts. From such an individualistic standpoint, a question of guilt or innocence must be resolved on the basis of the degree of responsibility for consequences, which can be measured, not the magnitude of intent to injure, which cannot. Thus it appears, after all, that there is some merit to the so-called “presumption of innocence” principle and none whatsoever for punitive damages. Consequently, the question of moral turpitude is irrelevant to restitution. Yet, according to Galambos, restitution is the criterion of justice. Curiously then, justice need not invoke moral considerations.
Since judicial processes cannot rely on a factual determination of guilt of malicious intent, punitive damages awarded in the course of so-called civil cases and fines and other punishments imposed in so-called felony matters are clearly arbitrary exactions from the accused. The operation of the “peoples” court in rendering such opinions to effect a sanction of enforcement inevitably spreads the responsibility for the damages, actual or potential, to “the public” whereby the conflict is not so much resolved as it is diluted. This is true whether the opinion is rendered by a jury collectively practicing one form of nose-counting or another (as if a majority vote could substitute for observational truth) or by a wise and learned officer of the court acting in good conscience.
Punishment for “sin” is not a human province. Behavior that is at odds with nature receives condign punishment in nature in due course without the benefit of human intervention. Vindication of the “right” by human resort to retribution after the fact of injury constitutes an initiative act of force based on synthetic or superhuman authority. Science offers no prospect of elevating mere human beings to such an authoritarian status by any means whatsoever.
This is not to say that there is no such thing as intent to injure, or that when humans commit injurious acts against their fellows it means nothing more than when the other animals do. In fact, as pointed out by Grannis, intent is inherent in the volitional phenomenon as indicated by the etymology of the word. Thus,12 “intent,” whatever it is, must be considered a universal mental factor underlying all voluntary human action. It is just that one can never KNOW “intent” with enough confidence to justify retaliation tit for tat — an eye for an eye, etc. Restitution promotes rationality whereas retaliation and retribution promote only victimhood and enmity.
This position may appear naive in consideration of historical practices and what we generally refer to as a “right” (i.e. a legitimate authority) to react forcefully in self-defense against aggression. Self-preservation is inherent in all living organisms and there is no doubt a strong psychological attachment among humans to the IDEA of being vindicated “right” (i.e. morally righteous) and punishing “wrongdoing.” This drive suggests it may be important to distinguish between what is truly human from what is commonly animal. That was the idea behind Spencer Heath’s proposal to distinguish “society” as a certain peaceful, reciprocal and productive population within the human population at large.13 Galambos’“moral island” and “spaceland” metaphors might also be fitted into this paradigm.
So here’s where we need to refine our definition of volition or humanity so that we can know when we are dealing with animal behavior generally and human behavior specifically. This is a problem because we humans have a dual nature. We are switch hitters. We can all revert to our animal origins under certain circumstances. Sex and politics are cases in point. So are street brawls, gun fights, fisticuffs and contact sports.
DIFFERENTIATING SCIENCE FROM IDEOLOGY
An authentic science of volition should be able to shed light on when it is appropriate for humans to behave in accordance with their animal or social natures, and what are the specific circumstances that apply in either case. Also, the science should be able to predict the consequences free of any preconceived moral coloration.
Distinguishing science from ideology is a matter of differentiating between critical study and impassioned belief. How we study a part of the world is both complemented and impaired by how we believe the world to be. This challenge to intellectual honesty was well put recently by a couple of biology-oriented computer scientists:
There is a distinct difference between choosing a particular point of view for exploring a problem and insisting that a particular viewpoint is the only correct description. There may even be good methodological reasons to argue for caricature in a given instance. One of the things that frustrates non-scientists about the practitioners of science is their willing but fickle embrace of caricature. This methodological stance — simplify until forced to do something else — is generally justified by pointing to the productivity of a given simplification: it generates testable hypotheses….. [to which] we can add nuance by including ever more constraints and connections…. thus placing epicycles on epicycles. In this direction lies a top-heavy and unworkable theory. So we return to a simpleton version…. which can provide a [testable] hypothesis generating machine, not just a story-rationalizing machine.14
I offer these views merely to suggest that there are still other dimensions to be accounted for in what Galambos has referred to as “spaceland.” Perhaps it would be useful to think of “flatland” as the critter world and to “spaceland” as the human domain. I don’t think Abbott would take offense at this characterization.15 However, this application of Abbott’s imagery might well be inconsistent with what Galambos had in mind.
What is “capitalism?” Galambos considered it an ideology. It must be. After all, the word ends with “-ism.” Linguistics aside, capitalism can also be seen as a social or economic technology. How should that concept be named? Capitalogy?
According to one knowledgeable observer:
Capitalism produces wealth; it makes people richer than any other system. Capitalism we define as merely a state of nature…where people are free to go about their business based on customary, consensual rules in an evolved, vernacular market system. The more you tamper with it, the less well it works.16
CLOSURE
There is no disrespect in recognizing that Galambos left unfinished business. Perhaps he was keeping some things he knew to himself and overlooked a few things we now find important. In any event, it is safe to say that the development of volitional science will never be “finished.”
After all, Galambos was only human and it does him no credit to treat him otherwise. This is a good time of year (Easter) to be remembering this fact. It is entirely conceivable to me that Jesus might have meant more to the race had he not been deified by his disciples and “churchified” by his adversaries. Richard Nesbit, an early FEI lecturer, once referred to this phenomenon in his presentation of Course 100 as “church-ianity.” Galambos was not amused but Nesbit’s point was clear.
END NOTES
1 Cohen, Morris R. and Ernest Nagel, Introduction to Logic and Scientific Method,” Harcourt, Brace &
Co., 1934.
2 Joseph A. Galambos, “Why Does a Company Which Practices and Promotes Capitalism Call Itself
LIBERAL?” THRUST FOR FREEDOM–NO. 1, Los Angeles: The Liberal Publishing Co., 1962.
3 Andrew J. Galambos, “Capitalism, The key to Survival,” Course 100, Free Enterprise Institute, Los
Angeles, 1961.
4 Bastiat, Frederic, Social Fallacies [Economic Sophisms], Patrick James Stirling Translation. Santa
Ana, CA: Register Publishing Co., 1944.
5 Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto, 1847.
6 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Science#cite_ref-Thurs_3-0
7 Galambos, Andrew J., “The Theory and Protection of Primary Property,” Free Enterprise Institute
Course V-201.
8 Eddington, Arthur S. The Philosophy of Physical Science, pp. 16-27. University of Michigan Press,
1958,
9 Bridgman, Percy W., The Nature of Physical Theory, p.5. Princeton University Press, 1936.
10 Galambos, Andrew J., Sic Itur ad Astra. Coronado, CA: Universal Scientific Publishing Co., 1998.
11 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hamiltonian_mechanics
12 Grannis, Larry, “The Lexicon of Volition, ”E-mail L8, Saturday, 18 April, 1998, 01:40:21 -0700.
13 Heath, Spencer, Citadel, Market and Altar–Emerging Society. Elkridge, MD: Science of Society
Foundation, 1957. (Heather Foundation, Spencer Heath MacCallum, Intellectual Estate Trustee, sm@look.net; 713 W. Spruce St., Deming, NM 88030.)
14 Ahouse, Jeremy C. and Robert C. Berwick, “Darwin on the Mind — Evolutionary Psychology is in Fashion but is any of it True,” an essay review of Steven Pinker, How the Mind Works (W.W. Norton, 1998), p. 36, Boston Review, April/May, 1998.
15 Abbott, Edwin A., Flatland — A Romance of Many Dimensions. Sixth Edition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
1950.
16 Bonner, Bill, “Capitalism and the American Way,” The Daily Reckoning, London, England, Monday,
February 4, 2008.
_______________________________________________________________
Spencer Heath Archive
Item 3077
September 18, 2014
GOVERNMENT AS A MARKETABLE SERVICE
Some Recent History in the
Propagation of this Idea
Alvin Lowi, Jr.[i]
September 18, 2014
The announcement of a MISES CIRCLE seminar, “Society Without a State: Law and Order in a Free World,” to be held on November 8, 2014 has stirred much interest in the “total alternative” to tax-funded government, to use F. A. (“Baldy”) Harper’s phrase. Sixty years ago, about 1955, Baldy counted on the fingers of one hand the people he knew of in the world besides himself who entertained the idea.[ii] Today probably there are tens of thousands. Yet the history of the idea’s inception and spread, where known at all, is clouded. I met Spencer Heath in 1961 through Andrew J. Galambos,[iii] and because I was associated with Galambos’ Free Enterprise Institute, I was privileged to witness and participate in one of the least known parts of that spread, which it is the purpose of this essay to record.
Mises Daily on March 25, 2006 republished J. Huston McCulloch’s 1977 translation of a remarkable 1849 essay in French entitled The Production of Security. The author of this essay was an obscure laissez faire economist from Belgium named Gustave de Molinari, a contemporary and intellectual kinsman of the better known French liberal political economist Frederic Bastiat. McCulloch’s relatively recent English translation includes an inspiring introduction by Murray Rothbard. [iv]
Gustave de Molinari (1819 – 1912) was born in Belgium and educated there in the new academic field of economics. He was associated with the French “économistes”, a group of laissez-faire liberals recognizable nowadays as pro-capitalist libertarians. Throughout his long life (he was 92 when he died), Molinari argued for peace, free trade, freedom of speech, freedom of association, and liberty in all its forms.
Molinari was unique among economists in his conviction that the economy did not need even constitutionally limited government protection. He was apparently the first intellectual to discover this possibility and advance a theory of society entirely devoid of political regimentation, i.e. a stateless society. His vision of a stable and humane social paradigm takes individual human liberty to the limit. It is a condition libertarians nowadays call individualist anarchy, market anarchism, or anarcho-capitalism. Society without political statecraft has also been variously referred to as economic government, voluntary government, or government via market-delivered property protection services.
Andrew J. Galambos came to think likewise a century later, and apparently without a prompt from Molinari. Galambos was an astronomer and astrophysicist who left the government-dominated defense industry in 1959 at the height of the Cold War to make the world safe for astronauts. While still a tenured professor in physics he launched his campaign, “Capitalism, The Key to Survival,” in 1960 as a profit-seeking education business in Los Angeles under the banner of The Free Enterprise Institute (FEI). Galambos was an enthusiastic promoter of the writings of Rothbard and Mises. In the early 1960s, he brought Mises, LeFevre, MacCallum, and F.A. Harper to Southern California for seminars. He died in 1997 after a long illness. Some of his taped lectures were transcribed and published in 1999 as Sic Itur ad Astra, http://www.amazon.com/Sic-Itur-Ad-Astra-Volition/dp/0880780045/sr=1-2/qid=1160671190/ref=pd_bbs_2/102-3770766-9772913?ie=UTF8&s=books
It is curious that at the time of McCulloch’s translation, Galambos and Rothbard, who were ideologically and intellectually congenial in most respects, are seen to be going in opposite ideological directions, opposite in terms of Molinari’s “two ways of considering society.” Molinari put legislation and society (force and voluntary exchange) in separate worlds where they belong. But by the time McCulloch’s translation of Molinari’s Production of Security essay appeared (New York: Center for Libertarian Studies, 1977), Rothbard had already turned toward politics for social salvation. He was influential in the formation of the Libertarian Party in 1973[v]. Had Rothbard taken Molinari’s advice to heart, he would not have taken this direction. Partisan politics was not recommended by Molinari. In fact, such a course of action was contrary to his vision of the future.
While Rothbard and his libertarian colleagues were preoccupied with their political project, Galambos in Southern California was building ideological momentum for his non-political “natural republic,” which he envisioned as a societal condition comprised of voluntary behavior based on economic and ethical knowledge developed via an authentic science of society (dubbed “Volitional Science”). It would evolve through the market process, gradually replacing all coercive political institutions with voluntary, entrepreneurially-delivered property protection services.
At the outset of his venture, Galambos had been obsessed with American constitutionalism, which represented to him the break with traditional political despotism that enabled the liberation and growth of humanity as exemplified in what Alexis de Tocqueville and others considered “the American phenomenon.”[vi] Galambos had approached constitutionalism as an intellectual game to be played with organizational structures to contrive political strategies for limiting the scope of monopoly political government in keeping with the sentiments of the Declaration of Independence and other classical liberal arguments. However, no matter how liberal, creative or ingenious were these social contrivances of grand human design, they were inevitably political and therefore authoritarian and collectivistic, an implication not lost on Galambos’ students. Curiously, it was such implications in Ayn Rand’s “Objectivism” and Leonard Read’s “libertarian limited government” that alienated Galambos from those largely compatible social movements. Galambos defended his approach to constitutional political government with the claim that scientific method could be relied upon to avert the usual outcomes from political administration. Separation of economy and state was a central feature. The physicist cum economist would see to it.
Galambos’ teachings of laissez faire led to the inescapable conclusion that stable and progressive social institutions originated in voluntary human behavior and free association giving rise to autonomous specialization and exchange. Accordingly, whatever governmental institutions would come about would be by market demand subject to the spontaneous natural social order. Thus arose the contradiction presented by subsuming a free society under traditional American constitutionalism.
Reading the history and content of Molinari’s essay recalls the debates that occurred among the students of Galambos in the early days of the Free Enterprise Institute. Logical extrapolations of Galambos’ earliest teachings had begun to reveal inconsistencies in the classical liberal treatment of society that called for a modicum of political government to maintain a legal framework of order based on private property protection. Such protection was presumed to require an authority that was superior to the market, i.e. a supernatural authority. “The Constitution” has symbolized this supernatural authority in America.
About this time, 1963, Robert LeFevre came onto the Free Enterprise Institute scene. His arguments reduced all political proceedings to absurdity.[vii] They were being heard and brought back into the discussions at FEI by some of Galambos students attending LeFevre’s lectures at the Freedom School in Colorado.
Galambos conceived government as nothing more than the collection of services devoted to the protection of private property. It should not have been such a huge leap of faith, therefore, to dump the political paradigm altogether in favor of property protection services rendered volitionally for profit in the marketplace by competitive private enterprise. Yet, Galambos was not the first to leap. The idea began to catch on first among his students. The initial awakening took place soon after the first offering of his Course 100 in 1961 in which he sanctioned limited political government. I reckon the sequence of discoveries occurred thereafter as follows.
Anthropologist Spencer Heath MacCallum gave a guest course for FEI in 1963 in which he introduced the idea of a proprietary community.[viii],[ix] His approach followed the work of his grandfather Spencer Heath, who would have presented the concept to Galambos’ students a year earlier but for the intervention of a health crisis that ended his long life. Later, MacCallum also introduced E.C. Riegel’s The New Approach to Freedom to the FEI market, which suggested that laissez faire competition in the marketplace is necessary and sufficient government.[x] Riegel’s concept of “private enterprise money” was another inspiration MacCallum brought into the discussion of a wholly voluntary society.[xi]
In his FEI guest lectures the same year, F.A. Harper introduced Molinari’s vision of unregimented society to Galambos’ market.[xii] He was able to offer the attendees of his seminar some rare copies of Molinari’s only book in English at the time entitled Society of Tomorrow.[xiii] Harper billed Molinari’s proposal as a “total alternative” to the status quo — an emergent “grand alternative” to political government.
Out of this general inquiry came various private enterprise extrapolations. First to my knowledge was the “the insurance industry is government” proposal of physicist-mathematician and FEI contractor Piet Bos.[xiv] Next came a vision of competing companies providing dispute resolution, patrol, security technology, and bounty hunting services for fee or subscription as proposed by electrical engineer/entrepreneur/FEI contractor Charles R. Estes. Estes also proposed various private enterprise money and property restitution ventures.[xv] Subsequently, Andrew Galambos came out with his Course V201 containing his concept of the pure contractual corporation operating a clearinghouse for businesses utilizing intellectual property for profit. Galambos claimed this business would dispense with political government forever. Finally, Robert Klassen, another FEI contractor, published his treatise Economic Government.[xvi]
In 1964, some FEI contractors teamed up with FEI to bring Robert LeFevre to Los Angeles to give his seminar.[xvii] By this time, many of Galambos’ students had already shunned political government even as a transient lesser evil, preferring to take their chances with self-government in the marketplace, and eventually Galambos himself abandoned all political artifice. By 1968, he was espousing pure free-market social organization in which government was defined as follows:
“A government is a person or an organization that offers for sale products or services designed to protect property, to which the owner of that property may voluntarily subscribe.” [xviii]
Galambos called attention to his use of the article “a” in this definition: “a” government, not “the” government, emphasizing the absence of monopoly as an essential attribute.
The Mises Institute web page editor refers to Molinari’s vision as “anarcho-capitalism.” This libertarian term of art is an unfortunate choice, since it suggests Molinari’s brand of capitalism is without rules of order. It also misleads the reader by implying that Molinari’s proposal has some sort of political significance, at least an anti-state argument. Not so. Molinari is among the select few to abstain from any political contentions and pretensions whatsoever.
Galambos’ intellectual descendent Klassen used the term “economic government” to characterize the voluntary alternative in government affairs. Klassen’s term is more descriptive of Molinari’s positive prospect of security as a product of private enterprise operating in a wholly voluntary environment. This term is actually more to the point of Molinari’s proposal than his own title Production of Security, since “economic government” recognizes the important social contribution of proprietary administration in the practical realization and maintenance of a public service in a wholly voluntary society. Molinari, Heath and ultimately Galambos agreed on this point.
Molinari says that “There are two ways of considering society.” He explains the “first way” as follows:
According to some, the development of human associations is not subject to providential, unchangeable laws. Rather, these associations, having originally been organized in a purely artificial manner by primeval legislators, can later be modified or remade by other legislators, in step with the progress of social science. In this system the government plays a preeminent role, because it is upon it, the custodian of the principle of authority, that the daily task of modifying and remaking society devolves.
Initially, Galambos’ approach to society inclined toward Molinari’s “first way,” described above. He continued in this direction even after he became aware of Molinari’s treatise, Society of Tomorrow, which was given to him by his esteemed guest lecturer, F. A. Harper. Galambos was convinced that authentic social science (as he defined it), which came to be known as “volitional science” (named by Jay S. Snelson), would provide the legitimate authority and technology for designing and implementing the mechanisms, organizations and practices for the proper operation of society in the future. He believed his society of the future would be a technological achievement, which would lead to a wholly voluntary society in which every person would have 100% control over his own property, a condition he defined as freedom. Thus he would build a regime he called “the natural republic” (named by me) in a step-by-step process according to a design rendered beforehand, much as an architect would build a skyscraper — an analogy attributed to Galambos’ architect father Joseph B. Galambos.[xix] The contractors of the architect would come to the task by way of an ideological program, one which the architect offered as a proprietary product. Thereby freedom would be “built” or perhaps manufactured as a product by developing property protection and selling it as a product protected by intellectual property defense mechanisms, which Galambos disclosed in his Course V-201, “The Theory and Protection of Primary Property.”
While Molinari also talked about “production of security,” he rejected “social engineering” which Galambos, on the other hand, seemed to embrace in his ideological program. Galambos’ approach after he dispensed with political structures did fit the description of Molinari’s first way of considering society.
Galambos emphasized comprehensive property protection as the keystone of human society, and he relied on competitive private enterprise for profit to deliver the service. This idea was consistent with Molinari’s “second” approach, described by him as follows:
“According to others, on the contrary, society is a purely natural fact. Like the earth on which it stands, society moves in accordance with general, preexisting laws. In this system, there is no such thing, strictly speaking, as social science; there is only economic science, which studies the natural organism of society and shows how this organism functions.”
Notwithstanding Molinari’s rhetorical dismissal of “social science,” his organic view of society is remarkably consistent with Spencer Heath’s “Socionomy.”[xx] Whether Heath ever encountered Molinari’s writings is unknown. But in his treatise, Heath defines his “Socionomy” as follows:[xxi]
“Socionomy is the theory or formulation of the organic laws exemplified in the organization and development of society (Webster’s New International Dictionary).”
He also defined society as a natural phenomenon consisting of the strictly voluntary interactions of humans, advocating acceptance of it and learning how to get along in it as it is. Heath considered that his “socionomy” qualified as an authentic “natural science of society” because it produced dependable social technologies.
Molinari continues his explanation of his second approach as follows:
“We propose to examine, within the latter system [“economic science”], the function and natural organization of government – The Natural Order of Society. In order to define and delimit the function of government, it is first necessary to investigate the essence and object of society itself. What natural impulse do men obey when they combine into society? They are obeying the impulse or, to speak more exactly, the instinct of sociability. The human race is essentially sociable. Like beavers and the higher animal species in general, men have an instinctive inclination to live in society.”
Here Molinari depicts society as the natural habitat of man. That concept was familiar to students of Galambos according to FEI contractor Eric Szuter, who was inspired to choose it as his dissertation topic for a PhD in “Human Ethology.”
Molinari asks: “Why did this instinct [to live in society] come into being?” Galambos would object to such a question on the grounds that “why” questions do not qualify for scientific investigation because they call for theological answers, and he confessed he did not know anyone who could talk to God, the presumed creator of the universe. Galambos insisted that science, reliably informed by what can be gleaned of reality by the senses, can only deal with “how” questions. Thus, he would put Molinari’s question in a scientific context as “How did this instinct develop?” Molinari was quite prepared to answer this question as well, offering a splendid series of observations as follows:
“Man experiences a multitude of needs, on whose satisfaction his happiness depends, and whose non-satisfaction entails suffering. Alone and isolated, he could only provide in an incomplete, insufficient manner for these incessant needs. The instinct of sociability brings him together with similar persons, and drives him into communication with them. Therefore, impelled by the self-interest of the individuals thus brought together, a certain division of labor is established, necessarily followed by exchanges. In brief, we see an organization emerge, by means of which man can more completely satisfy his needs than he could living in isolation. This natural organization is called society.”
This argument demonstrates that Molinari was able to practice some dignified social science notwithstanding his dismissals of the notion.
Late Hayek is consistent with this view,[xxii] and Mises’ economics is consistent as well.[xxiii] But their indulgences in “political economy” are problematical because of the connection with policy, i.e. public policy. Public policy has to do with the governance of the political authority that presumes to reign over society. Mises accepted a “limited” political monopoly (state) control of the means of defense, property protection and justice — by “law” of course. Sadly, however, practical limits to political government are unknown to man. Madison’s heroic attempts in The Federalist Papers to set forth public policies to be embodied in a constitution for a republic of defined and limited powers over the people of the United States of America are a poignant case in point.
The nature of man and his government is a long-studied and little-understood subject in the human curriculum.[xxiv],[xxv],[xxvi] Molinari was perhaps the first person to make a persuasive case for evolutionary natural social organization, which is the grand alternative to a Platonic political state. Hopefully, with the relatively recent spread of economic knowledge and know-how, it will not take economic government 5000 years to overtake political government of about that age.
/Materials deleted from the foregoing:/
[Galambos’ teachings of laissez faire capitalism in the early days of the Free Enterprise Institute had led to the inescapable conclusion that stable and progressive social institutions originate in voluntary human behavior and free association, giving rise to autonomous specialization and exchange between individuals and their proprietary organizations. Accordingly, whatever governmental institutions might come about in the prospective free society would be by market demand subject to the spontaneous natural social order. How to square this natural outcome with his proposed “engineered” free society (called a natural republic), let alone his politically “free” society under limited constitutional government, was a high intellectual challenge. The natural outcome eventually won out on the strength of Ockham’s Razor.]
End Notes
* The proletariat. from the Latin proletarius, meaning a citizen of the lowest class, is a term used to designate the lowest social class. It became Marxist jargon for the working class in the emerging industrial world of the 19th Century. A member of such a collective of people is a proletarian, originally identified as those people who had no wealth other than their children. Marx’s proletarians owned nothing but their undifferentiated physical labor, which doomed them in his view of the world to perpetual wage slavery. As a result, they would need a socialist state as he prescribed for protection from the greedy capitalists. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Proletariat Thus, the national state is conceived as a protection racket.
[i] Alvin Lowi is a mechanical engineer and thermodynamicist in private practice in Rancho Palos Verdes, CA. He has written many articles on free-market subjects and for ___ years (19__-19__) was senior lecturer at the Free Enterprise Institute in Los Angeles.
[ii] Personal communication from Spencer MacCallum. The other four were Heath, MacCallum, LeFevre and Rothbard. While appreciating the frequent difficulty of knowing how ideas are originated or transmitted, Baldy thought possibly it had come to him from a typescript of Heath’s Citadel, Market and Altar that John Chamberlain had sent him a year before it was clearly in his mind, and that from him it may have been transmitted to LeFevre and Rothbard. He suggested MacCallum ask Rothbard about it, but MacCallum did not follow up.
[iii] Alvin Lowi, “The Legacy of Spencer Heath: A Former Student Remembers the Man and Offers Some Observations on the Scientific Orientation of His Work,” January 3, 2001. <alowi@earthlink.net>
4 “Weekend Read, MisesDailyArticle.org, March 25, 2006. The complete essay in English is at http://mises.org/story/2088#6.
[v] _____________, “Exclusive Interview With Murray Rothbard,” http://www.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard103.html . [Originally published in The New Banner: A Fortnightly Libertarian Journal on 25 February 1972. Thanks to J. Michael Oliver for sending it to the Mises Institute. Thanks also to W. Robert Black III, of the New Banner Institute.
[vi] Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, Vintage Books, 1945.
[vii] Robert LeFevre, “Must We Depend on Political Protection?—Yes…Edmund A. Opitz, No…Robert LeFevre,” Studies in Human Action, Vol. II, No. 1, The Pine Tree Press, The Freedom School, Colorado Springs, CO, 1962.
[viii] Spencer Heath, Citadel, Market and Altar. Baltimore: Science of Society Foundation, 1956.
[ix] Spencer H. MacCallum, The Art of Community. Menlo Park, CA: Institute for Humane Studies, 1970.
[x] E.C. Riegel. The New Approach to Freedom. San Pedro, CA: Heather Foundation, 1976.
[xi] E.C. Riegel. Flight From Inflation: The Monetary Alternative. Los Angeles: Heather Foundation, 1978.
[xii] F. A. Harper was a professor of economics at Cornell University and a staff economist with the Foundation of Economic Education. He founded the Institute for Humane Studies, a community of libertarian scholars now located at George Mason University.
[xiii] Gustave de Molinari, The Society of Tomorrow. London: T. Fisher Unwin, 1904.
[xiv] Peter B. Bos, “The Societal Implications of Risk Sharing,” Draft of December 20, 1998. Pbbos@aol.com
[xv] Charles R. Estes, Voluntary Exchange: Keystone of Civilization. San Diego, CA: Mary L. Estes, 1997.
[xvi] Robert Klassen, Economic Government, http://www.amazon.com/gp/product/0595174035/103-7536333-3895865?v=glance&n=283155
[xvii] Robert LeFevre, “The Thinking Man’s Guide to Politics,” Seminar. Los Angeles: Free Enterprise Institute, May 2, 1964.
[xviii] Andrew J. Galambos, Sic Itur ad Astra. Page 138. San Diego, CA: Universal Scientific Publishing Co., 1999.
[xix] Suzanne Galambos, More Lasting than Bronze. Coronado, CA: Universal Scientific Publishing Co., 1991.
[xx] Spencer Heath, Citadel, Market and Altar. Baltimore: The Science of Society Foundation, 1956.
[xxi] Spencer Heath, op. cit., page 231.
[xxii] Friedrich A. Hayek, Denationalization of Money—The Argument Refined. Third Edition. London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1990.
[xxiii] Ludwig von Mises, Human Action. Yale University Press, 1954.
[xxiv] Leonard Read, Government – An Ideal Concept, Foundation for Economic Education, 1954.
[xxv] Robert LeFevre, The Nature of Man and His Government, Caxton Printing, 1959.
[xxvi] Theodore J. Lowi, American Government: Incomplete Conquest, Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1976.
Metadata
Title | Correspondence - 3077 |
Collection Name | Spencer Heath Archive |
Series | Correspondence |
Box number | 19:3031-3184 |
Document number | 3077 |
Date / Year | 1961-2014 |
Authors / Creators / Correspondents | Andrew Joseph Galambos |
Description | Galambos correspondence – to, from or about Andrew J. Galambos |
Keywords | Galambos Correspondence |